LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENCE: RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE'S THEORY

Page created by Hector Oliver
 
CONTINUE READING
LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENCE: RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE'S THEORY
Alberto De Luigi

LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE
OF DIFFERENCE:
RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE’S
THEORY • PART II

                               per a
                                ngp
                             rki
                           wo

    Centro Einaudi
N2 2015   ISSN 2036-1246
ALBERTO DE LUIGI

   LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENCE:
       RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE’S THEORY

                               PART II

Centro Einaudi • Laboratorio di Politica Comparata e Filosofia Pubblica
               with the support of Compagnia di San Paolo

                   Working Paper-LPF n. 2 • 2015
2                                                         WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

                 © 2015 Alberto De Luigi and LPF • Centro Einaudi

Alberto De Luigi graduated in Political Science at the University of Milan (2012)
writing the thesis La neutralità: Charles Larmore e il liberalismo politico. He is currently
attending the international Master degree program in Economics and Political
Science at the University of Milan. While dealing with political philosophy, his
main interest is to offer a non-ideological vision of political liberalism that may
conciliate the communitarian and libertarian drifts, leading them towards a shared
perspective, founded on the principle of equal respect.
                              albertodeluigi@outlook.com

The Comparative Politics and Public Philosophy Lab (LPF) at Centro Einaudi
is directed by Maurizio Ferrera and funded by Compagnia di San Paolo. It includes
the Welfare Laboratory (WeL) and the Bioethics Lab (La.B). LPF analyses the
transformation of the political sphere in contemporary democracies with a focus on
the relationships between policy choices and the value frameworks within which
such choices are, or ought to be, carried out. The reference here is to the “reasonable
pluralism” singled out by John Rawls as an essential feature of political liberalism.
    The underlying idea is that implementing forms of “civilized” politics is desirable
as well as feasible. And, as far as the Italian political system is concerned, it is also
urgently needed, since the system appears to be poorly prepared to deal with the
challenges emerging in many policy areas: from welfare state reform to the governance
of immigration, from the selection criteria in education and in public administration
to the regulation of ethically sensitive issues.
    In order to achieve this end, LPF adopts both a descriptive-explanatory approach
and a normative one, aiming at a fruitful and meaningful combination of the two
perspectives. Wishing to foster an informed public debate, it promotes theoretical
research, empirical case studies, policy analyses and policy proposals.

                              LPF • Centro Einaudi
                        Via Ponza 4 • 10121 Torino, Italy
                             phone +39 011 5591611
             segreteria@centroeinaudi.it • http://www.centroeinaudi.it
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II    3

                                     T ABLE OF C ONTENTS

LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENCE:
RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE’S THEORY • PART II

Introduction                                                                                           5
1. Strict and lax reading of the difference principle                                                   5
2. Inconsistency between maximin rule and difference principle                                          7
3. Long term expectations and contractualist theory                                                     9
4. Complex terms condition and primary goods                                                           12
5. Representation of the difference principle                                                          14
6. Indeterminacy and the four-stage sequence                                                           17
7. The right of property in Rawls’ theory                                                              20
Conclusions                                                                                            23
References                                                                                             28

                 Part I of this paper has been published as WP-LPF 2/14
   (http://www.centroeinaudi.it/images/abook_file/WP-LPF_2_2014_De%20Luigi.pdf)

                                            K EYWORDS
        John Rawls, Charles Larmore, political liberalism, difference principle,
                             neutrality, theory of justice
4                                                      WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

                                     A BSTRACT

               LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENCE:
               RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE’S THEORY • PART II

John Rawls’ Political Liberalism (1993) is considered a turning point in the theory of
the famous author, but certain elements of his theory, as they were presented in
his previous work A Theory of Justice (1971), might appear unclear under a liberal
perspective, in particular with regard to the interpretation of the highly debated
difference principle. In the first part of this paper—published in this WP-LPF
Series—, it is exposed the theory of political liberalism, with particular attention to
the concept of neutrality as formulated by Charles Larmore; this precedes the
analysis of the principles of justice in Rawls’ philosophy: an important aim of this
work is to offer a key to understand the revision of Theory, which can be found
reading Charles Larmore’s Patterns of Moral Complexity (1987), a book also studied
and commented by Rawls. Starting from the common elements which bind the
two said authors, it is explained why Rawls borrows a lot from the theory of the
younger philosopher, even underlining the references they make to each other’s
works. The whole second part would focus on this thesis: how the difference
principle, as proposed by Rawls in A Theory of Justice, could conform itself to the
features of political liberalism theory.
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   5

        LIBERALISM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DIFFERENCE:
        RAWLS TESTED BY LARMORE’S THEORY • PART II

INTRODUCTION

Charles Larmore rises some doubts about the justifiability of the difference princi-
ple: in order to justify it, it is necessary to abandon the idea that the principle
expresses our deepest personal ideals (conception that Rawls seems to embrace in
Theory, instead). Larmore continues:
    A more promising approach might be to base the neutrality of this principle on more
    purely political considerations […]. Everyone agrees that the state must play some role
    in regulating the distribution of wealth, and so such intervention must be neutral with
    regard to the interests of rich and poor. Whether this will suffice to ground the differ-
    ence principle, of course, is a more complex question, involving both normative and
    economic considerations. My aim is not to answer it here (indeed, it is rightly contro-
    versial whether this particular welfarist principle should be upheld, and the answer may
    be negative). My aim is to indicate how the question should best be discussed. (Lar-
    more 1987, 129)
It is possible to neutrally justify the difference principle in the perspective of
political liberalism, and this is the main issue dealt with in this essay. Explaining
how to justify John Rawls’s principle under a liberal perspective is a necessary
premise in order to justify Rawls’s political liberalism, since his revisited theory in
Political Liberalism maintains the same fundamental principles of A Theory of Justice
almost unchanged. This means that elements already present in Theory, like the
difference principle and the conception of primary goods, can be understood in
a neutral way with respect to comprehensive conceptions of the good life. The
interpretation provided in this paper outlines a clearer and lucid vision of Rawls’
theory of justice as fairness.

1. STRICT AND LAX READING OF THE DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE

The second principle of justice states that “the social and economic inequalities are
to be arranged so that they are both (a) reasonably expected to be to everyone’s
advantage, and (b) attached to positions and offices open to all” (Rawls 1971, §11,
6                                                            WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

60). Rawls later specifies (§46, 302) that the point (a) refers to “the greatest benefit
of the least advantaged” (members of the society): this coincides with the differ-
ence principle. As Valeria Ottonelli (2010, 107) writes in Leggere Rawls, this means
that “egalitarian measures need to be implemented to the point where any further
step in the direction of egalitarian order would be counter-productive, in the sense
that would worsen the condition of the lower classes rather than improve it”. The
affirmation is correct, but the problem is that the limit above which additional
measures become counter-productive (for those situated in the worst conditions)
would leave a redistribution leeway much smaller than assumed by the interpreters
more fascinated (or frightened) by the tension of the egalitarian theory of Rawls.
Secondly—and this is the crucial point—the “condition of the lower classes” is
understood in complex terms and not as a single dimension (like income or wealth
in monetary terms), nor as a single dimension at a time—even in the practical
application of the principle!—but is considered “as a whole”. Therefore it is
necessary to analyse what should be the correct interpretation of the principle of
justice.

It is first necessary to distinguish between a “weak” and a “strong” reading of the
difference principle.1 This distinction is already outlined by Andrea Villani in
Giustizia Distributiva e Scelte Collettive, who refers to the difference principle writing:
    … the strong reading that inequalities (e.g. in the distribution of income) shall be al-
    lowed providing that they result in only an aid to disadvantaged, or rather in the weak
    sense [...] that inequalities are permissible providing that they result also (necessarily,
    but not only!) in an aid to the disadvantaged, which is radically different. (Villani 1988,
    204, translation mine)
Villani explains why he supports the second interpretation, starting from the
analysis of the “principle of redress”: it would be related with the difference prin-
ciple because the last “gives a certain weight to the consideration singled out by
the principle of redress” (Rawls 1971, §17, 100). Rawls explains that, according to
the principle of redress, “undeserved inequalities call for a redress; and since ine-
qualities of birth and natural endowment are undeserved, these inequalities are to
be somehow compensated for” (p. 100). But, in spite of what seems to be derived

    1 It is even the opinion of Cohen in Rescuing Justice and Equality, who speaks about the
“strict” and “lax” readings of the principle, underlining the “ambiguity” of Rawls: “… the
difference principle, which endorses all and only those social and economic inequalities that
are good for the worst off or, more generously, those inequalities that either make the worst
off better off or do not make them worse off: in this matter there is a certain ambiguity
of formulation in Rawls. […] We confront here two readings of the difference principle: in
its strict reading, it counts inequalities as necessary only when they are, strictly, necessary,
apart from people’s chosen intentions. In its lax reading, it countenances intention-relative
necessities as well. So, for example, if an inequality is needed to make the badly off better off
but only given that talented producers operate as self-interested market maximizers, then
that inequality is endorsed by the lax, but not by the strict, reading of the difference princi-
ple. I shall argue that each of these incompatible readings of the principle is nourished by
material in Rawls’s writings, so that he has in effect two positions on the matter” (Cohen
2008, 29, 69).
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   7

from the general principle, Rawls argues with an example that “in pursuit of this
principle greater resources might be spent on the education of the less rather than
the more intelligent, at least over a certain time of life, say the earlier years of
school” (p. 100). Furthermore, the difference principle does not require that natu-
ral endowment to be levelled off: it doesn’t require that “the society attempts to
abolish disability, as if everyone should run the same race from a fair starting
point” (p. 100). This approach seems very evasive and restrictive compared to the
enormous subversive tension of the values inherent in the principle of redress.
Nevertheless, Villani insists that strictly speaking also a principle of justice like
the redress one does not seem to bring equality, like Rawls says (in the above
mentioned quotation) and also like Plattner thinks. Quoting Mark Plattner (1979),
Villani concludes that “despite the egalitarian premises and opposition to the mer-
its, in fact the expectation (made explicit) [in Theory] is towards a society not much
different from the present USA one” (Villani 1988, 112). In the following pages
it would be explained why the only possible way to understand the difference
principle is through the comprehension of what Villani called weak reading. A dif-
ferent interpretation (like the strong reading) would lead to the conclusion that
Rawls cannot be an exponent of the liberal tradition, and this for sure would be a
serious mistake.

2. INCONSISTENCY BETWEEN MAXIMIN RULE AND DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE

The “Rawlsian social welfare function”, as it is commonly known by economists
and reported in textbooks2 (graph in Figure 1), is not suitable to explain Rawls’s
ideas; on the contrary, if used with this purpose, it would be absolutely misleading.
If we conceive a conception of justice based on Figure 1, we would upset what
expressed in A Theory of Justice, where the illustration of the difference principle
is more complex (see Figure 2 in paragraph 5, taken directly from Rawls) and
combined with some basic considerations that are not negligible. It is necessary
to immediately clarify that the difference principle and the maximin rule are two
distinct elements, and confusing one with the other is incorrect. As Rawls states,
“Despite the formal resemblance between the difference principle as a principle of
distributive justice and the maximin rule as a rule of thumb for decisions under
uncertainty […], the reasoning for the difference principle does not rely on this
rule. The formal resemblance is misleading” (Rawls 2001, §27, 94-95). In note
(n17) he adds: “the failure to explain this was a serious fault in Theory.” And again:
“it is not essential for the parties to use the maximin rule in the original position.
It is simply a useful heuristic device. Focusing on the worst outcomes has the

    2 For example Scienza delle Finanze, by Harvey S. Rosen and Ted Gayer (third Italian edition

2010, ed. Chiara Rapallini), refers to Rawls and the original position, reporting at p. 142: “he
also states that in the initial situation the citizens would choose a social welfare function based
on the criterion of the maximin, because this is a kind of insurance against the most disastrous
outcomes” (translation mine) and draws a graph similar to that shown in Figure 1.
8                                                        WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

advantage of forcing us to consider what our fundamental interests really are when
it comes to the design of the basic structure” (Rawls 2001, §28.3, 99). As Rawls
himself points out, various authors mixed up the topic: “the maximin rule was
never proposed as the general principle of rational decision in all cases of risk and
uncertainty, as some seem to have thought. For example, see J.C. Harsanyi, in his
review essay, «Can the Maximin Principle Serve as a Basis for Morality?»” (Rawls
2001, §28, 97, n19); and again: “Instead of «the difference principle», many writers
prefer the term «the maximin principle» [...] But I still use the term «difference
principle» to emphasize first, that this principle and the maximin rule for decision
under uncertainty (§28.1) are two very distinct things; and second, that in arguing
for the difference principle over other distributive principles […] there is no ap-
peal at all to the maximin rule” (Rawls 2001, §13, 43, n3). All the passages men-
tioned are extracts from Justice as Fairness, but they even apply to A Theory of Justice;
in fact, as Rawls states, the difference principle does not change: “The revisions in
the second principle are merely stylistic” (Rawls 2001, §13.2, 43).

                                        Analysing the graph in Figure 1, the in-
                                        compatibility between the actual Rawlsian
                                        principle and its incorrect representation
                                        comes easily to light. Assume that u1 is the
                                        utility of the individual who is better, u2
                                        of the one who is worse; I, II and III are
                                        indifference curves (for the same level of
                                        social welfare). If a curve is higher than the
                                        other, it expresses a greater social welfare.
                                        The distribution of goods in society would
                                        determine a point within the quadrant,
                                        located on one of the indifference curves of
social welfare, and which identifies a given utility for the individual corresponding
to u1 and for the one corresponding to u2. For the present, we assume the
hypothesis that what is represented is utility, in general terms. Actually for Rawls
is not so, as widely explained hereinafter, since he doesn’t deal with utility, but
primary goods. To semplify, we can speak of utility “if we assume utilities to be
linear in indexes of primary goods” (Rawls 2001, §62, 62). Now, according to the
chart, you notice that:

1. if the utility of the individual who is worse decreases because of the increasing
   utility of the individual better situated, you move on a curve located below.
   Therefore, to maximize social welfare, it is not possible to increase the utility of
   an individual if this is at the expense of the individual who is worse;
2. it is indifferent, in the calculation of social welfare, increasing u1 if this increase
   does not correspond to an increase of u2. This is because the social welfare is
   equal to the utility of the individual who is worse.

This seems directly deductible from the second principle of justice, for this reason
it is often equated to the maximin. But according to Rawls’s discussion of the dif-
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   9

ference principle, for each point listed above you should make an important ob-
servation:

1. Rawls assumes that it is not possible (at least “up to a certain point”) increasing
   u1 (who is better situated) without even u2 increases;
2. since it is not possible increasing u1 without a resulting increasing of u2, it
   would never be different increasing u1, since this increase would always benefit
   the individual who is worse, at least “up to a certain point”.

Rawls’s assumption is absolutely fundamental. He states what follows:
    as we raise the expectations of the more advantaged the situation of the worst off is
    continuously improved. Each such increase is in the latter’s interest, up to a certain
    point anyway. For the greater expectations of the more favored presumably cover the
    costs of training and encourage better performance thereby contributing to the general
    advantage. (Rawls 1971, §26, 158)

The principle doesn’t force to an egualitarian arrangement. Rawls doesn’t consider
as indifferent (as instead it would result from the maximin) an increasing of u1 on
equal terms of u2 (who is worse off), which enhances inequality between the two.
Rather, he states that, precisely in virtue of the principle, “it must be reasonable
for each relevant representative man […] to prefer his prospects with the inequali-
ty to his prospects without it” (Rawls 1971, §11, 64). The same concept is repeated
in Justice as Fairness, §18.2, and again: “This is because over time the greater returns
to the more advantaged serve, among other things, to cover the costs of training
and education, to mark positions of responsibility and encourage persons to fill
them, and to act as incentives”; and further: “plainly the difference principle […]
recognizes the need for inequalities in social and economic organization, of which
their role as incentives is but one” (Rawls 2001, §19.2, 68). These passages are the
foremost confirmation of Andrea Villani’s idea of weak reading of the principle:
“inequalities are permissible providing that they result also (necessarily, but not
only!) in an aid to the disadvantaged”.

3. LONG TERM EXPECTATIONS AND CONTRACTUALIST THEORY

The reason why increasing utility of the individual who is better off would lead to
an improvement of those who are worse off can be more accurately explained
as follows. Of course, if we had a cake to be shared between two individuals, and
we start giving more slices to those who are better off, as a consequence it would
remain less available to those who are worse; but the assumptions behind Rawls’
considerations are very different, since the condition of representative3 individuals
must be considered under these circumstances:

    3 “When principles mention persons […] the reference is to representative persons […]

I assume that it is possible to assign an expectation of well-being to representative individuals
10                                                           WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

1. by means of a reasoning that takes into account the expectations in the long
   term, not the immediate allocation of resources;
2. in complex terms, through an index of primary goods.

Rawls doesn’t deal with utility, but only with expectations. To clarify what he
means with the term “expectations”, he introduces the concept of primary goods.4
In Justice as Fairness he specifies that “the index of primary goods [that are the sub-
ject of the distribution] is an index of expectations for these goods over the course
of a complete life” (Rawls 2001, §51.5, 172). If expectations are meant for the
whole of life, certainly justice as fairness doesn’t treat the question of immediate
allocation of income. In addition, as would be discussed hereinafter, the choice
between different distributions of primary goods is restricted to the choice of
some different schemes of cooperation (i.e. anarcho-capitalist system or a more
regulated welfarist system). These schemes of cooperation may include anarcho-
capitalist systems as well as more regulated welfarist systems. In this sense, to
choose the right scheme is a different issue with respect to the choice on how
to allocate resources already available.

Anyway, it can be demonstrated that, with regard to the distribution, even consid-
ering only the mere income rather than an index of primary goods (thing that even
Rawls does in some exemplifications), the criterion of maximin is not appropriate
to explain the difference principle. The reason is that the legislator (or anyway the
one who chooses how to redistribute) must be in the original position to deliber-
ate. The veil of ignorance implies that the “persons in the original position have
no information as to which generation they belong. These broader restrictions on
knowledge are appropriate in part because questions of social justice arise between
generations as well as within them” (Rawls 1971, §24, 137). Therefore it is suffi-
cient to consider the conditions imposed by the original position to conclude that
it’s improper to raise an argument concerning only the short term. Instead, it’s
correct to subsume a variety of topics that go far beyond the pure economic ones,
even when the decision is right on the redistribution of income, rather than an in-
dex of goods. In fact, the psychology and the motivational law (taken into account
under the veil of ignorance, as Rawls himself states (Rawls 1971, §24, 137-138)
leads to formulate policies far more complex than the immediate monetary (or
material) compensation for the disadvantaged.

In a broader view, deducting wealth (even just in the monetary sense) from the
rich to give to the poor may, in the long run, damage (right in monetary terms)
the poor themselves. The ambition, the hopes of reaching a better condition or
the benefits of competitive struggle are elements that play a crucial part in this

[…]. This expectation indicates their life prospects as viewed from their social station. […]
neither principle applies to distributions of particular goods to particular individuals who may
be identified by their proper names” (Rawls 1971, §11, 64).
    4 In fact the §15 (p. 90) of A Theory of Justice titles “Primary Social Goods as the Basis of

Expectations”.
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   11

context. A strong redistribution can increase the utility of those who are worse off
(and therefore the social welfare) in the short term, but it could also worsen the
situation in a broader context. In this sense, the limit for which more egalitarian
measures would be counter-productive becomes much lower than what assumed
in “the strong reading” of Rawls’s principle of justice. An excessive state aid can
lead, over time, to a loss of utility of individuals who are just immediately advan-
taged (or only for the present). In this regard, as Rawls says: “I shall not consider
how far these things are true. The point is that something of this kind must be
argued if these inequalities are to be just by the difference principle” (Rawls 1971,
§13, 78). For these reasons, Figure 1 is not pertinent in order to consistently
explain the difference principle. Rawls in fact raises an entirely different issue, for
which the criterion of maximin is totally inadequate:
    the difference principle is not intended to apply to such abstract possibilities. As I have
    said, the problem of social justice is not that of allocating ad libitum various amounts
    of something, whether it be money, or property, or whatever, among even individuals.
    Nor is there some substance of which expectations are made that can be shuffled
    from one representative man to another in all possible combinations. (Rawls 1971, §26,
    157-158)

To allocate ad libitum a certain quantity of goods is instead a matter of allocative
justice (see even Justice as Fairness, §14 titled “The Problem of Distributive Jus-
tice”). To allocate resources between individuals with given preferences concerns
utilitarianism rather than the contractualist theory of justice as fairness. Villani
makes this point clear when he refers to the analysis of Salvatore Veca in “Utilita-
rismo e contrattualismo. Un contrasto tra giustizia allocativa e giustizia distributi-
va”: “Veca defines utilitarianism as a theory of allocative justice and contractualism
a theory of distributive justice […] The allocative justice subsumes, we can say, an
«instantaneous» way of giving resources, concerning individuals (i.e. preferences)
with no space for their history, nor the relations between them” (Villani 1988,
235-236, translation mine). Therefore, unlike utilitarianism, which tries to allocate
resources or goods between individuals with given preferences and in a precise
moment, the question posed by the theory of justice as fairness instead leads to
evaluating the principles that form a stable cooperation between individuals or
groups over time. The condition of the community, which in case of utilitarianism,
or allocative justice, is assumed, in case of contractualism, or distributive justice, is
central because it is itself a subject of social choice (see Veca 1986, 114). The
choice on the “condition of the community” implies a way to weigh individual
preferences, that is defining legitimate and illegitimate interests of citizens. This
could also suits various utilitarians: in fact, as noted by Villani, all utilitarians but
Bentham, including Harsanyi, tended in some way to weigh individual preferences
before including them in the “social calculation”.5 However Villani (1988, 234)
says that normally utilitarians pose no formal criteria to define legitimate and ille-
gitimate interests, and to distinguish between them. Veca states:

    5   “Calcolo sociale” in the original.
12                                                           WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

     The contractualist theory proposes, in other words, to answer the question remained
     open for utilitarianism of preferences of Harsanyi: can you find a criterion of legitima-
     cy about preferences and interests? [...] It is not the simple fact that we have prefer-
     ences, or that we are centres of pleasure or pain and we have goals, but the fact that we
     are able to reason about preferences that we happen to have, and while doing so, we
     recognize the others as similar to us, and therefore worthy of equal respect:[6] recurring
     issues of distributive justice are at the core of a contractualist approach”. (Veca 1986,
     108, 116, 117, translation mine)

Rawls provides afterwards good evidence to confirm Veca and Villani’s insights—
they wrote in the eighties, before the publication of Political Liberalism; hence their
reference was only A Theory of Justice. In Justice as Fairness, he writes: “Observe that
particular distributions cannot be judged at all a part from the claims (entitle-
ments) of individuals earned by their efforts within the fair system of cooperation
from which those distributions result. In contrast to utilitarianism, the concept of
allocative justice has no application” (Rawls 2001, §14.2, 50-51); and then speci-
fies: “the two principles of justice incorporate the concept of pure background
procedural justice and not that of allocative justice” (Rawls 2001, §51.4, 170-171).

In conclusion, it’s possible to say that contractualism lies “upstream” of utilitarian-
ism, namely it rises issues that have priority on the matters posed by utilitarianism
and which are very constitutive of the basic patterns of morality (and the basic
structure of society). It is first necessary to establish what is the condition of the
community and what are the legitimate or illegitimate interests; once established
that, the foundations laid down by the theory of justice as fairness, then the issues
raised by utilitarianism can be put under consideration or to the vote. Utilitarian-
ism would be considered as one of the various comprehensive conceptions of
good, to which the doctrine of political liberalism must remain neutral, ensuring
coexistence with other comprehensive conceptions.

4. COMPLEX TERMS CONDITION AND PRIMARY GOODS

The above was the discussion on the first assumption of the difference principle:
the fact of taking into account the expectations in the long term. The second
assumption that shall be analysed is the conditions considered in complex terms,
through an index of primary goods. In the theory of justice as fairness, with regard
to the problems of distributive justice, Rawls makes use of the concept of expecta-
tion, not utility. The expectations are not composed by the satisfaction that citi-
zens believe they are capable to get through the available goods. If so, the index of
primary goods should embrace all persons’ conceptions of good. Instead, primary

     It can be excluded that Veca refers to Charles Larmore’s ideal of equal respect (Patterns of
     6

Moral Complexity is published afterwards, in 1987), but it is very interesting to note how the
basic intuition is exactly the same.
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   13

goods are not determined on the basis of an amount of satisfaction they yield
when employed, so they don’t depend on specific conceptions of good, nor they
determine conceptions in any way. They are only means that citizens, in the meas-
ure they can get them, can use (or not, if they prefer not to) to pursue their own
conception of good. Primary goods are, in a nutshell, the social values of “liberty
and opportunity, income and wealth, and the social bases of self-respect” (Rawls
1971, §11, 62). So the condition of the least advantaged is meant in complex
terms, not about a single dimension (for example only income or properties), and
the way inequality can be “redressed” concerns the redistribution of all these social
values as a whole.

However, it might be objected that, applying the redistribution considering in
complex terms all dimensions at the same time (income, self-esteem, fundamental
liberties, etc.), there’s a risk of reducing Rawlsian principles of justice to total inde-
terminacy. Therefore, while applying the second principle of justice, it’s plausible
to distinguee among different dimensions and apply it limited to a single dimen-
sion at a time. Sometimes, for practical purposes, it may happen to consider only
one dimension at a time, like income, but certainly it’s not the case when is pre-
sented any objection to proceed in this way. A good argument against an applica-
tion of the principle calculating only one dimension at a time is suggested by the
analysis of §51 of Justice as Fairness: “The flexibility of the index of primary goods”,
where Amartya Sen’s ideas—exposed in Choice, Welfare, and Measurement (Sen 1986,
353-356)—are commented by Rawls: “primary goods themselves should not be
viewed as the embodiment of advantage, since in fact advantage depends on a
relation between persons and goods” (Rawls 2001, §51, 168). Here Rawls empha-
sizes that the index of primary goods he proposed “does not take into account,
and does not abstract from, basic capabilities” (Rawls 2001, §51.2, 169); on the
contrary, it “fully recognizes the fundamental relationship between primary goods
and persons’ basic capabilities. In fact, the index of those goods is drawn up by
asking what things, given the basic capabilities included in the (normative) concep-
tion of citizens as free and equal, are required by citizens to maintain their status as
free and equal” (Rawls 2001, §51.2, 169-170), including civil and political liberties
and so on. Provided this, if the worth of a good is based on the ability of an indi-
vidual, and if those capabilities also depend on other goods like liberty or oppor-
tunity (as it is intuitive), unlikely it would be completely abstracted from the over-
all vision of the index of goods and considering a dimension at a time. Moreover,
considering that the choice of the society is restricted to different feasible schemes
of cooperation (as explained below), it would be absurd to grant to a representa-
tive individual a combination of primary goods formed by an amount of income
and social bases of self-respect defined ad libitum. These goods would be closely
connected to each other within a certain scheme of cooperation and therefore on-
ly certain combinations would be achievable, namely the one given (or feasible) for
each scheme. Rawls takes a stand to support these arguments:
    Yet it seems extraordinary that the justice of increasing the expectations of the better
    placed by a billion dollars, say, should turn on whether the prospects of the least fa-
14                                                             WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

     voured increase or decrease by a penny. […] Part of the answer is that the difference
     principle is not intended to apply to such abstract possibilities. The possibilities which
     the objection envisages cannot arise in real cases; the feasible set is so restricted that
     they are excluded. The reason for this is that the two principles are tied together as one
     conception of justice which applies to the basic structure of society as a whole (Rawls
     1971, §26, 157-158).

5. REPRESENTATION OF THE DIFFERENCE PRINCIPLE

As just mentioned in the quotation above, the two principles are tied together as
one conception of justice applying to the basic structure of society as a whole. In
fact, one last point to underline is that the difference principle cannot be consid-
ered independently from the other principles of justice. The principle of equal lib-
erty in general is already implicitly included in the difference principle, since liberty
is one of primary goods. The first principle comes into play only when it is neces-
sary to give liberty an order of priority over other primary goods and “this priority
rules out exchanges («trade-off», as economists say) between the basic rights and
liberties covered by the first principle and the social and economic advantages
regulated by the difference principle” (Rawls 2001, §13.5, 47). The first principle
could simply be a kind of clause of the second, which specifies that, among prima-
ry goods, fundamental liberties have a “utility” so great that, whatever combina-
tion of goods is obtained, the individual deprived of liberty is considered the one
worse off.

This particular view of the two principles helps a better comprehension of how
the difference principle operates. In fact, thanks to this explanation, it’s easier to
imagine both Rawls’ principles as illustrated in the next figure that would be ana-
lysed (the illustration of the difference principle, see Figure 2) and thus to convey
a broader outlook over the Rawlsian theory of justice. The clause, anyway, is rele-
vant since it is not absurd to speak about utility of liberties or other elements of
primary goods, like Rawls does: “these liberties are the same for all citizens (are
specified in the same way) and the question of how to compensate for a lesser lib-
erty does not arise” (Rawls 2001, §45.1, 149). In fact, Rawls distinguishes between
the freedom as “equal liberty” and the “worth of liberty”7 (Rawls 1971, §32, 204),
just as if it couldn’t be assigned any worth to “equal liberty”. On the contrary, the

     7In a nutshell, we can say that the concept of equal liberty defines a balanced scheme of
fundamental liberties (which are political ones, as it is wider explained in Justice as Fairness
(Rawls 2001, §45, 148 and following): to ensure a particular liberty requires to restrict or regu-
late another, so it is necessary to organize a system of liberties that depends on the totality of
limitations they are subjected to. This system is guaranteed as exactly alike for all, according to
the first principle. Instead the worth of liberty can vary, for example: the ones who are richer
can take more advantage of their own liberty of opportunity, in this sense it has a greater
worth. The worth of liberty depends on the index of primary goods and is governed by the dif-
ference principle.
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   15

hypothesis supported in this paper is that, focusing the attention on a single prin-
ciple of justice (the second, plus the clause derived by the first), the worth of
“equal liberty” would simply be so high that it cannot be compared to the “value
of liberty” nor the one of other primary goods. Now, it is clear that Figure 1 (in-
troduced above and related to the maximin criterion) is not suitable to illustrate
the difference principle at all. Therefore, below is shown the illustration of the dif-
ference principle as it appears in A Theory of Justice (or Justice as Fairness, where there
is only the graph on the right, see Figure 2). The path followed up would be useful
in order to immediately understand the mechanics in the chart. Initially it was in-
troduced the hypothesis that improving the expectations of the more advantaged,
the level of those who are worse off rises continuously. Furthermore, for each rel-
evant representative individual “must be reasonable to prefer his own prospects
with the inequality rather than his prospects without it” (Rawls 1971, §11, 64) and
“the difference principle […] recognizes the need for inequalities” (Rawls 2001,
§19.2, 68). Therefore, starting from the picture of the criterion of maximin, we
have to consider only the part of the figure consisting in those points (assuming
that x1 is the individual who is better) that are located to the right of the bisector,
which corresponds to all points of perfect equality. It makes no sense to consider
indifferent that our own condition is placed in whatever point on the curves of
social welfare shown by the graph on the left (see Figure 2), as implied by the
maximin. In fact, we know that increasing utility (meant as a linear function of
primary goods) of x1, then even utility of x2 improves, thus leading the society to a
curve of greater social welfare.

The curve OP (P stands for production) is given for a certain scheme of coopera-
tion. There are different curves OP, more or less efficient, among which the socie-
ty can choose. For example, we can imagine a libertarian and anarcho-capitalist
scheme of social cooperation, or at the opposite a welfarist scheme more inclined
to state aid policies, each of them with its own curve OP. The fact that the choice
is restricted to different “schemes of social cooperation” (i.e. different OP curves)
excludes that it’s possible to choose among different allocations ad libitum. In fact,
even x1 and x2 are “specified by reference to their shares in the output and not as
particular individuals identifiable independently of the scheme of cooperation”
(Rawls 2001, §18, 63). The problem of distributive justice and the contractualist
16                                                      WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

doctrine of justice as fairness is precisely to identify which scheme, or curve OP, is
more efficient and to reach the higher point “a” on this curve. The term “scheme
of cooperation” used by Rawls is rather generic, but we may assume that a curve
can vary from one to another simply thanks to the introduction of a legislative
reform. In order to choose the best alternative, we know that one “scheme is
more effective than another if its OP curve always gives a greater return to the less
advantaged for any given return to the more advantaged” (Rawls 2001, §18, 63).
The return, as seen above, can be measured as utility, that is a linear function of
the primary goods in complex terms, taking into account that the choice of coop-
eration excludes those systems which do not guarantee fundamental liberties,
according to the priority of the first principle. In other words: utility would fall
dramatically if these liberties were not guaranteed, excluding in this way that par-
ticular scheme rather than others. It may be that the priority of the first principle
does not appear justifiable in certain cases. The first principle about priority of
liberty, in fact, can be considered (although Rawls doesn’t express the concept
in these terms) part of the difference principle, as a clause stating that the utility
attributed to fundamental liberties is so high that they are not exchangeable with
other primary goods. Under certain conditions, it appears unreasonable and it may
prevent the principles of justice from being justified in certain societies, like for
example those in which there is an extreme lack of resources, since there it might
seem justifiable to exchange some liberties with other primary goods. In fact, in
conditions of extreme need in which it is difficult to ensure the survival of indi-
viduals, it might appear unfair to prevent someone from the voluntary exchange
of some liberties for other primary goods (like food). But it should be noted
that Rawls’ principles of justice suite only a society which remains in a condition
of moderate scarcity. This is an assumption of the whole Rawls’s theory: “the cir-
cumstances of justice obtain whenever mutually disinterested persons put forward
conflicting claims to the division of social advantages under conditions of moder-
ate scarcity. Unless these circumstance existed there would be no occasion for the
virtue of justice” (Rawls 1971, §22, 128). This is a fundamental point, without
which it would be difficult to justify, aiming to an overlapping consensus, the
principles of justice, especially the priority of liberty.

In order to choose the fairest scheme, we have to look at which one reaches the
highest line among the “equal-justice lines” (Rawls 2001, §18.1, 62) that are the
part of the indifference curves situated at the right of the bisector. When utility of
the individual who is better off grows too much, then “even though the index
[of primary goods] increases for the more advantaged group […] the reciprocity
implicit in the difference principle no longer obtains” (Rawls 2001, §18.1, 62-63).
As Rawls specifies (p. 62), the alternatives in which the total utility is higher (where
is maximized the sum of utilities, the Bentham point, or the product, the Nash
point) do not represent the best result for the theory of justice as fairness nor for
the difference principle. In fact, when a curve OP begins to fall after having
reached the highest point (i.e. after touching the line of higher justice), it means
that an increase of utility of those who are better off no longer leads also to an
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   17

improvement of those who are worse. Beyond this point (the threshold), if the in-
dividuals who are better off enrich themselves more, it would be necessary to re-
distribute their income to those who are worse off (ceteris paribus for what regards
the other primary goods, and therefore assuming that the fact of the redistribution
doesn’t harm the fundamental liberties). In order to identify the threshold, it is
necessary to understand exactly what primary goods are in practice.

6. INDETERMINACY AND THE FOUR-STAGE SEQUENCE

Rawls offers a list of primary goods rather generic, and in Justice as Fairness (Rawls
2001, §51) confirms the flexibility of the category. The application of the differ-
ence principle to concrete cases would lead to unpredictable consequences if the
index of primary goods is considered as a whole, rather than one dimension at a
time (i.e. income, liberties and so on). H.L.A. Hart (1975) criticizes the indetermi-
nacy in Rawls’s concept of liberty and, as stated by Valeria Ottonelli in Leggere
Rawls, he “pointed out that the principle remains completely undetermined: it is
not clear which liberty should be guaranteed, and to what extent, until the citizens
of a well-ordered society (and the parties in the «original position») will specify a
list of purposes and activities that should enjoy special protection” (Ottonelli
2010, 95, translation mine). The reference is to Rawls’ first principle of justice, but,
as said, if the liberties of the first principle are not accurately determined, this ap-
plies exactly in the same way to the difference principle, given that liberty is part of
primary goods. Such criticism highlights even more how much Rawls’s concept
of primary goods appears obscure and, consequently, problematic in practice.

Actually, the indeterminacy of the index is not a problem in Rawls’s theory, but a
fundamental feature of it, without which the theory of justice as fairness would be
even contradictory. In fact Rawls replies to Hart’s criticism specifying a list of fun-
damental liberties (Rawls 1993, VIII, §1, 292) that can be achieved in two ways:
historically and analytically. Nevertheless, the key point is not the list itself, since
“the discriminating power of philosophical reflection at the level of the original
position may soon run out. When this happens we should settle on the last pre-
ferred list and then specify that list further at the constitutional, legislative, and
judicial stages, when general knowledge of social institutions and of society’s cir-
cumstances is made known” (Rawls 1993, VIII, §1, 293). Thus the liberty would
be specified in different stages and so, by analogy, even the rest of primary goods
(and in general the index as a whole) could be specified in this way.

This idea of various stages resembles the “four-stage sequence”, namely the
framework that Rawls adopts in order to “simplify the application of the two prin-
ciples of justice” (Rawls 1971, §31, 195). Therefore it’s plausible that the index of
primary goods should be determined by a gradual development of the four stages
in a practical way.
18                                                             WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

     Each stage is to represent an appropriate point of view from which certain kinds of
     questions are considered. Thus I suppose that after the parties have adopted the prin-
     ciples of justice in the original position, they move to a constitutional convention […]
     It is at this stage that they weigh the justice of procedures for coping with diverse polit-
     ical views. Since the appropriate conception of justice has been agreed upon, the veil
     of ignorance in partially lifted. (Rawls 1971, §31, 196-197)

The four stages are: the original position, the constitutional convention, the legis-
lative stage, while the last is “the application of rules to particular cases by judges
and administrators, and the following of rules by citizens generally” (p. 199). It
is important to note that at this last stage “everyone has complete access to all
the facts. No limits on knowledge remain since the full system of rules has now
been adopted and applies to persons in virtue of their characteristics and circum-
stances” (p. 199).8 Therefore primary goods, basically, would be determined in
light of all general economic and social facts of a particular society, in a given situ-
ation. The veil of ignorance is already partially lifted in the constitutional conven-
tion stage, and even more, when the difference principle is applied in the other
stages, contingent situations should be carefully considered, including the presence
of various conceptions of good in the society and their own features.

The argument supporting the four-stage sequence is that “men’s judgments and
beliefs are likely to differ especially when their [of the citizens] interests are en-
gaged. Therefore secondly, a citizen must decide which constitutional arrange-
ments are just for reconciling conflicting opinions of justice” (Rawls 1971, §31,
195-196). Rawls’s theory offers a method to mediate among these interests (name-
ly among different conceptions of the good) without proposing an alternative to
these conceptions, as it might be a very specific list of primary goods. The purpose
of the theory is in fact more general: ensuring neutral conditions so that the index
of goods may actually be the result of a social agreement, in which the contracting
parties can assert their opinions and conceptions of the goods. In fact, pure pro-
cedural justice (such as the original position9) does not intend to express a certain
conception of good, but the political process shall be considered “as a machine
which makes social decisions when the views of representatives and their constitu-
ents are fed into it”; the purpose of this machine is to “rank procedures for select-
ing which political opinion is to be enacted into law” (Rawls 1971, §31, 196). And
    8 Rawls associates the first principle of justice to the stage of the constitutional conven-

tion, the second to the legislative one: “The first principle of equal liberty is the primary
standard for the constitutional convention. […] Thus the constitution establishes a secure
common status of equal citizenship and realizes political justice. The second principle comes
into play at the stage of the legislature. […] At this point the full range of general economic
and social facts is brought to bear. […] Thus the priority of the first principle of justice to the
second is reflected in the priority of the constitutional convention to the legislative stage”
(Rawls 1971, §31, 199).
    9 The original position is a “case of pure procedural justice”, as Rawls explicates in Political

Liberalism (1993, II, §5.2, 73). The subject is widely treated in the Theory §14, where it is speci-
fied that the justice as fairness intends to “apply the notion of pure procedural justice to dis-
tributive shares” (1971, §14, 86).
Alberto De Luigi • Liberalism and the Principle of Difference: Rawls Tested by Larmore’s Theory / II   19

these opinions, as observed, are determined by the conceptions of the good:
judgments, beliefs and interests. For this reason, primary goods are determined by
the social contract. This method perfectly suites the idea of neutrality as exposed
in Charles Larmore’s political liberalism. Therefore, in order to apply the index of
primary goods in a factual context, we must move to further steps beyond the
original position, up to the point where we have to vote (decide by voting) on the
matter in question in a particular case.10 Even at the legislative stage the “proposed
bills are judged from the position of a representative legislator who, as always,
does not know the particulars about himself” (Rawls 1971, §31, 198), therefore a
partial veil of ignorance remains. However, the representative legislator must
choose, or mediate, among “proposed bills”, which comes from citizens (or their
representatives) with different conceptions of good. In some cases, we may even
consider that what is called here “representative legislator” could be simply a
machine that counts votes, and the measure that has the majority passes, provided
that the statutes meet “not only the principles of justice but whatever limits are
laid down in the constitution” (p. 198).

The concept of index of primary goods therefore remains undetermined, but it
could not be otherwise, if the theory of justice as fairness shall remain coherent.
As Rawls says: “on many questions of social and economic policy we must fall
back upon a notion of quasi-pure procedural justice […]. This indeterminacy in
the theory of justice is not in itself a defect. It is what we should expect” (Rawls
1971, §31, 201). There is disagreement among liberal and reasonable thinkers even
on constitutional principles, while the difference principle, which should not
appear even in a constitution (it cannot have legal value, and it must be a sort of
preamble to the constitution instead11), can be compared to a kind of aspiration—
so to speak—which would inspire the legislature. The only stages in which there is
no reasonable disagreement are: the original position (where each conception of
the good is excluded from the veil of ignorance), the overlapping consensus (by
definition), the general formulation of the principles of justice and, consequently,
the idea of using the primary goods, rather than utility or other parameters, as an

    10 In Justice as Fairness Rawls proposes the case of a parliamentary measure that allots public

funds to preserve the beauty of nature in certain places. According to the principles of political
liberalism, it is possible that arguments in favour of such a measure can be sustained on the
basis of specific conceptions of good, as they could be perfectionism or utilitarianism: “some
arguments in favour may rest on political values […] political liberalism with its idea of public
reason does not rule out as a reason the beauty of nature as such or the good of wildlife
achieved by protecting its habitat. With the constitutional essentials all firmly in place, these
matters may appropriately be put to a vote” (Rawls 2001, §46.2, 152, n26).
    11 Rawls in Justice as Fairness: “A second worry is whether the fulfilment of the difference

principle should be affirmed in a society’s constitution. It seems that it should not, for this
risks making it a constitutional essential which the courts are to interpret and enforce, and
this task is not one they can perform well. Whether that principle is met requires a full under-
standing of how the economy works and is extremely difficult to settle with any exactness,
although it may often be clear that it is not satisfied. Still, if there is sufficient agreement on the
principle, it might be accepted as one of society’s political aspirations in a preamble that lacks
legal force (as with the U.S. Constitution)” (Rawls 2001, §49.5, 162).
20                                                             WP-LPF 2/15 • ISSN 2036-1246

indicator of what are the needs of free and equal citizens. However, the index of
the primary goods in a specific formulation suitable for application in factual con-
text would be determined only by the social contract at different stages, provided
that instances of the previous stages (the first is the original position) are observed.
Rawls does not say it clearly, but this process would also lead to the fact that
the social contract, in each stage, would determine the way in which the funda-
mental liberties, and consequently a specific characterisation of them, shall be
guaranteed. The index (and so even the fundamental liberties) does not corre-
spond to a conception of good supported by Rawls, nor anyone, in the original
position. Again, determining what are the liberties that “provide the political and
social condition essential for the adequate development and full exercise of the
two moral powers of free and equal persons” (Rawls 2001, §13.4, 45) is an issue
that does not appear immediate nor thinkable without consulting the most im-
portant conceptions of good in the society. Even if to enunciate these liberties
seems easy, the way in which they shall be regulated (under the constitutional,
legislative and jurisprudential stages) has serious implications on the real notions
underlying those enunciations.

7. THE RIGHT OF PROPERTY IN RAWLS’ THEORY

Let’s make an example regarding the right of property: it is a primary good since
it is included among the social basis of self-respect (Rawls 2001, §32.6, 114) (see
paragraph 4 of this essay). This right is historically highly discussed, from the liber-
tarian theory of the “entitlement” of Nozick (1974)12 to the Marxist or socialist
theories.13 The theory of justice as fairness promotes the property as the right “to
hold and to have the exclusive use of personal property” (Rawls 2001, §32.6, 114).
But how shall be determined this concept in light of the practical and normative
regulation of the right within the society? Would it be closer to the libertarian or
the socialist version, or again, entirely different from both? According to Rawls,
this concept does not exclude nor support the wider conceptions of “private
property” or “social property” of means of production and natural resources:
“these wider conception of property are not used because they are not necessary
for the adequate development and full exercise of moral powers, and so are not
an essential social basis of self-respect. They may, however, still be justified. This
depends on existing historical and social conditions” (Rawls 2001, §32.6, 114).
This underlies the fact that conceptions of the good of the society, varying from
one society to another, can lead to a very different choice of primary goods (in-
cluding the right to property), depending on the outcome of the deliberations

    12 It is clear that if the State applies any redistribution (except the eventual legitimation

given by the principle of rectification of injustice) is violating the principles of justice of the
entitlement theory.
    13 Rawls speaks about “equal right to participate in the control of the means of production

and of natural resources” (Rawls 2001, §32.6, 114).
You can also read