LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL: THE USE OF CONTRADICTIONS IN AN EXPERIMENTAL NOVEL ON THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF THEISTIC BELIEF

Page created by Jill Barrett
 
CONTINUE READING
ROCZNIKI HUMANISTYCZNE
                                  Tom LXII, zeszyt 5 – 2014

JOANNA KLARA TESKE *

               LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL:
 THE USE OF CONTRADICTIONS IN AN EXPERIMENTAL NOVEL
   ON THE EPISTEMOLOGICAL STATUS OF THEISTIC BELIEF

A b s t r a c t. The essay discusses Yann Martel’s Life of Pi, focusing on the novel’s use of contra-
dictions to present the theme of the theistic, atheistic and agnostic beliefs. The novel seems to
defend the thesis that theism is rational (on pragmatic rather than epistemic grounds), atheism in
its choice of commitment resembles faith, whereas agnosticism can be identified with dogmatic
materialism and a passive attitude towards life. To illustrate this view the novel engages the
readers in an experiment, offering them two mutually exclusive versions of Pi’s survival story.

Key words: Life of Pi, Yann Martel, contradictions, belief, cognition.

   The aim of this paper is to examine how contradictions function in a highly
experimental novel on epistemology of religion, Life of Pi by Yann Martel
(2001).
   The term “contradiction” is used here with reference to internal relations
between various elements of a work of art as well as relations between the
work and empirical reality (or, more precisely, the reader’s model of this
reality) that might be defined as those of contrast, incompatibility, conflict
or tension.1 This broad, “aesthetic,” interpretation of contradiction seems to
be an extension of its logical meaning: in logic, contradiction is defined as
the relation that obtains between two mutually exclusive propositions. This
is not to say, however, that translating aesthetic (often non-verbal) contra-
dictions into their logical (propositional) counterparts is always feasible.

   Dr. JOANNA KLARA TESKE—John Paul II Catholic University of Lublin, Institute of English
Studies, Department of English Literature and Culture; address for correspondence: Al. Racła-
wickie 14, PL 20-950 Lublin; e-mail: jteske@kul.pl
   1
     By analogy, “coherence” is used with reference to the same relations if they exhibit har-
mony, organic unity or compatibility.
280                                 JOANNA KLARA TESKE

    The novel by Martel deserves close attention in the context of contra-
dictions for two reasons: 1) it abounds in contradictions and many of these
lie at the heart of the cognitive experiment that the novel offers to the reader,
2) it provides solutions to many of its contradictions, 2 apparently restoring
the state of coherence.
    The major contradictions inherent in the book and their resolutions are as
follows:

                           1. CONTRADICTIONS
                 BETWEEN THE FIRST STORY OF PI’S SURVIVAL
                         AND EMPIRICAL REALITY

    The bulk of the novel is constituted by a first-person retrospective
account of Pi’s survival. This account is hard to believe as the 16-year-old
boy survives 227 days drifting on the Pacific in a lifeboat alone except for
the company of a Bengal tiger. The tiger’s name is Richard Parker (this
unusual name, as Pi explains, is the result of the shipping clerk’s error,3
175–7). Pi’s adventures include among others an accidental meeting of two
lifeboats “navigated” by two blind castaways in the middle of the ocean.
Finally, to crown the tale’s extraordinariness, there is a “predatory” island,
made of algae, inhabited only by meerkats and grown with carnivorous trees.
    All this sounds incredible but the story is “confirmed” by the words of the
“author,”4 who did his best to check what he had first heard from Mr Adi-
rubasamy (allegedly the “author” spoke in person also to Mr Patel and Mr
Okamoto); the descriptions are rich in detail, which adds to the effect of
veracity; frequently the reader’s newly revived doubts are dispelled with
suitable explanations (e.g. the tiger on the boat survives some time on ocea-
nic water but Pi, at first puzzled himself, remembers that indeed tigers from

   2
      To resolve a contradiction means here either to identify the mutually exclusive propositions
that are at stake and establish their logical value so that the false one may be eliminated, or to
transform the semantic context, e.g. from factual to fictional, so that the contradiction no longer
occurs.
    3
      Worth noting is also the intertextual character of the name, which is borrowed from Edgar
Allan Poe’s Narrative of Arthur Gordon Pym, as Martel admits (“‘The Empathetic Imagina-
tion’. . .” 26; cf. also David Ketterer).
    4
      By the “author” I refer here to one of the novel’s narrators whose note, titled “Author’s
Note,” precedes the text, and who in various ways resembles Yann Martel but should not be
identified either with the real or implied author (cf. Ines 26).
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                      281

the Sundarbans are known to drink saline water, 214); in some passages the
tone of the novel comes close to semi-documentary.
   Thus the novel tells an implausible story that is supposed to be true,
presenting its readers with a chance to probe their will to believe. 5 Sooner or
later, in spite of themselves, the majority will conclude that the story is
“false,” while the claim that it is “true” is part of the author’s game. Alter-
natively, to resolve the contradiction the readers may choose to trust the
implied author and believe the tale, ignoring their common sense.6

                           2. CONTRADICTIONS
                BETWEEN THE TWO VERSIONS OF PI’S SURVIVAL

   The story of Pi’s survival fails to satisfy Mr Okamoto and Mr Chiba, who
are investigating the sinking of the Tsimtsum. Seeing that the officials with
their critical rationalist approach remain sceptical, Pi offers them an
alternative story.7 The original story (“the story with animals”) and the later
version (“the story without animals”), both told by the same person, exclude
each other. Multiple parallels between the two accounts (e.g. in the former
the hyena eats the wounded zebra, in the latter the cook amputates the
Chinese sailor’s broken leg to use it as fishing bait and, after the man dies,
eats his flesh)8 do not change the fact that “the story with animals” shows Pi
as a pious man of integrity, who does not falter even when confronted with
the most exacting experiences, whereas in “the story without animals” Pi
loses his innocence: after the cook has murdered Pi’s mother, Pi murders
him and triumphantly eats his heart and liver.
   The problem of the conflicting narratives is solved by Pi’s argument that
since it is impossible to establish which version is true and neither explains

    5
       One might question this description of the novel’s strategy on the grounds that readers who
read fiction suspend their disbelief, i.e. they agree to be taken in, so the experiment cannot work: the
novel tests the readers’ suspension of disbelief, not credulity. Yet this objection need not be valid as
modern works of art frequently combine fictional and factual elements and readers may well discern
between them, hence their willingness to believe, to take fictional for factual, may be tested.
     6
       Apparently some readers take the story as “real” (cf. June Dwyer, 18–9).
     7
       The alternative story sounds more believable but it too contains weird elements (e.g. the
cook eats flies the first day after the shipwreck when there is plenty of food, 407) and fails to
account for some facts that the original story explains (e.g. the meerkats’ bones in Pi’s boat, 402–
3). Ines seems right to call the second version “allegedly more believable” (27).
     8
       Mr Okamoto obliges the reader by noting the parallels one by one (417–8).
282                                 JOANNA KLARA TESKE

the mystery of the ship’s sinking one should feel free to believe “the better
story.” The conflict is solved more definitely by Pi’s more radical suggestion
that human perception and interpretation of reality as well as human use of
language, which all involve an element of invention, transform human life
(human knowledge included) into a story (405).9
    The reader might, however, question this resolution of the contradiction.
First of all, even though the two Japanese officials and the reader do not know
the truth, Pi does know it,10 which weakens considerably his argument. Further,
the rational response to the situation in which one is presented with two con-
flicting accounts of equal epistemological status may well consist in concluding
that at least one of them is false, though neither needs to be true, and suspending
one’s judgment. This would be a wise course of action especially in a situation
of high emotional pressure. The novel omits to even mention this possibility.
Finally, even if it is true that all cognition involves an element of construction,
the suggestion that all representations of reality (scientific knowledge included)
are fictional and narrative seems highly contentious.

                        3. CONTRADICTIONS
              BETWEEN THE NOVEL’S CRITERIA OF CHOICE
        AS REGARDS THE TWO VERSIONS OF PI’S SURVIVAL STORY,
        APPLICABLE BY EXTENSION WHEN VARIOUS COMPETITIVE
                ACCOUNTS OF REALITY ARE AVAILABLE,
         AND THE STANDARD RATIONAL MODEL OF COGNITION11

  In the novel Pi names the criteria which encourage Mr Okamoto and Mr
Chiba to question the first version of his story: the story’s believability12 and

    9
       Cf. “Doesn’t the telling of something always become a story? [. . .] Isn’t just looking upon
this world already something of an invention? [. . .] The world isn’t just the way it is. It is how
we understand it, no? And in understanding something, we bring something to it, no? Doesn’t
that make life a story?”
    10
       The sobriety of Pi’s discourse makes the hypothesis of his mental instability and
corresponding lack of clarity concerning the true course of events unlikely.
    11
       The “standard” model is a concept I need to introduce here to be able to continue analyzing
the book in terms of contradictions. If the reader finds this notion disagreeable, the following
discussion may, I think, be read simply as a critique of the novel’s epistemology.
    12
       Cf. “If you stumble at mere believability, what are you living for? [. . .] Love is hard to
believe, ask any lover. Life is hard to believe, ask any scientist. God is hard to believe, ask any
believer. What is your problem with hard to believe?” (399–400).
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                      283

its consistence with one’s currently held beliefs,13 which might in fact amount
to one criterion: believability as consistence with one’s currently held beliefs.
Pi disapproves of this kind of conservative scepticism. The Japanese officials
try to justify their disbelief, arguing that Pi’s story contradicts facts, has no
support in sensory data, would be disqualified by science, does not comply
with the laws of nature and is very unlikely. Pi makes little of these objec-
tions: he denies that the story contradicts facts; the testimony of the senses, as
he says, is not always available; science has been known to err; one should not
presume to know the laws of nature “through and through”; low probability
does not prevent people from winning the lottery (395–6, 401).
    After presenting the alternative version of his story, Pi himself considers
the two versions in terms of three epistemic criteria—contradictoriness to
facts, explanatory power and verifiability—to conclude that the criteria are
of no use: they do not help differentiate between the two versions (424). So
that when Pi urges his listeners to choose “the better story,” it is not clear
what guidelines they should apply. The “better” might perhaps be identified
with the ability to expand one’s view of life (dismissing the believability
criterion, Pi suggests that a story can make you “see higher or further or
differently,” 406).14 It might also refer to richness in meaning or capability
of lending meaning to human life, as suggested by Pi’s words: “Where we
can, we must give things a meaningful shape” (383),15 though the imperative
is not recalled in this context. Charlotte Ines in turn suggests that the
criterion implied in the concept of the better story be interpreted in terms of
the artistic quality of the tale,16 which comes close to Martel’s own state-
ment: “The theme of this novel can be summarized in three lines. Life is a
story. You can choose your story. And a story with an imaginative overlay is
the better story” (qtd in Gregory Stephens, 42). Alternatively, one might
argue that the absence of a clear indication how to identify “the better story”
means that the choice should be made freely, according to one’s liking,
without reference to any specific criterion.

    13
         Cf. “You want a story that won’t surprise you. That will confirm what you already know”
(406).
    14
       Cf. also Cockeram’s interpretation: the novel shows how the ability to expand one’s world-
view makes a good story and constitutes the reason why the story should be believed.
    15
       Cf. Brian Thorpe: “’the better story’ [. . .] is not about facts but is, rather, about the role of
the power of symbols and human imagination to transcend day-to-day reality and to find meaning
and even glimpses of the divine” (51).
    16
       Cf. “[. . .] the tiger story is the finer, more thoughtful literary creation and therefore (Martel
suggests) has a truth more lasting than the second, more journalistic version [. . .]” (27).
284                                   JOANNA KLARA TESKE

    Thus, the novel’s epistemic criteria for assessing a belief seem to include
the following: correspondence with facts, explanatory power, verifiability
and ability to expand one’s view of life. These seem to be further supple-
mented with the ability to give meaning to human life and artistic/imagi-
native quality—i.e. pragmatic benefits and aesthetic values. Meanwhile the
standard model of rational cognition pays much attention to such criteria as
consistence with previously held beliefs, assessment of probability, assess-
ment of the strength of supporting evidence (these are mentioned in the
book, but their treatment is cursory and dismissive). Statements about things
that might theoretically be possible but are extremely improbable17 and chal-
lenge one’s view of life cannot rationally be taken as true on the testimony
of a single person. The divergence between the novel and the standard
rational approach as regards the criteria for choosing one’s beliefs remains
unresolved. The readers who spot it are left to their own devices.

                             4. CONTRADICTIONS
                  BETWEEN VARIOUS RELIGIONS ILLUSTRATED
                    BY PI’S MULTIPLE RELIGIOUS IDENTITY

   “But he can’t be a Hindu, a Christian and a Muslim. It’s impossible,”
argue the imam and the priest (92).18 They believe that the accounts of God
given by various religions are mutually exclusive. 19 Pi protests: “’All reli-
gions are true.’ [. . .] I just want to love God” (92). 20 The novel’s vision of

    17
        This impression of implausibility is the standard critical reaction to Pi’s tale, cf. William
Skidelsky: “Naturally, it is an entirely improbable scenario, but [. . .] the telling is so com-
pelling.”
     18
        Ines claims that the novel also contains references to the Jewish Kabbalist tradition in the
name of the ship (“Tsimtsum”), Pi’s choice of Isaac Luria as the subject of his religious studies
and those descriptions of Pi’s religious experience which correspond to Luria’s thought (cf. Ines’
paraphrase of Luria’s ideas: “[. . .] God’s light contracted from the center of the universe, purging
itself of evil elements, leaving an empty space (a circle) in which human life developed. But God
also sent down a ray of light [. . .] so that the few remaining divine sparks could reconnect with
Him. To achieve this fusion with God [. . .] people must live an ethical life. The original divine
contraction is called variously tzimtzum, zimzum or simsum,” 27).
     19
        Pi seems unaware of the fact, cf. Cockeram: “The specific doctrines of Pi’s three faiths
make very little difference to him. When comparing these religions to one another, Pi seems to
conclude in his innocence that there need not be conflict between them [. . .].”
     20
        Interestingly, to Pi’s confusion, his irreligious father replies that everybody strives to “love
God” (93) as if religion were not indispensable for that purpose.
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                     285

God and man’s religious experience focuses on love as an abstract prin-
ciple,21 as God’s love of man 22 and as man’s desire to love God.23 The God
of the novel seems both transcendent and absolute as well as immanent
(identical with the human ability to love and the experience of being loved).
The contradiction between various religions’ images of God and ways of
worshipping God might thus be resolved by reducing all religious experience
to its essence conceived of as love, with various religions “merely alter-
native paths to the same destination,” as Paul Cockeram puts it.24 The reader
may draw this conclusion on the basis of Pi’s religious experience. Pi’s
experience can also be interpreted as a choice of “religious eclecticism, or
syncretism,” as suggested by Eric Ziolkowski (42).25 But neither concentrat-
ing on the fundamental message of love, nor eclectic combining of various
devotional practices can solve doctrinal differences between religions. Pi’s
refusal to choose one religion may have various advantages (tolerance, rich-
ness of religious experience, etc.), but it entails embracing contradictions.26
    The contradictions lose their significance if religions are interpreted as
fictional narratives (if their doctrines are not taken to reveal the truth about
God). This indeed seems to be both Pi’s and, as it is inscribed in the con-
struction of the whole book, the implied author’s approach. When discussing
the two versions of his survival, Pi suggests that all man’s beliefs are to
some extent tales of man’s making and that given that two beliefs have equal
epistemic status, one should feel free to choose “the better ” (which might be
interpreted as a recommendation of the story that offers some non-epistemic
advantages). Then Pi notes: “And so it goes with God.” The analogy might

   21
       Cf. the “author’s” reflection that “the founding principle of existence is what we call love”
(84–5).
    22
       Cf. Pi’s resolution after the shipwreck: “so long as God is with me, I will not die” (197), or
his thoughts when he prepares for death: “And now I leave matters in the hands of God, who is
love and whom I love” (326).
    23
       Cf. Pi’s fear that an atheist’s words might “kill God in a man” (37) and Pi’s faith regained
after a moment of despair: “[. . .] God would remain, a shining point of light in my heart. I would
go on loving” (281).
    24
       Also Thorpe speaks of “this tripartite religious identity defended solely on the basis of
love” (54).
    25
       As he argues, “in lieu of some simpler, more conventional oath consisting of a single word
or name, the boy in The Life of Pi, whenever startled, exclaims: ‘Jesus, Mary, Muhammad and
Vishnu!’” (42). The same eclecticism might be spotted in Pi’s Canadian house furnished with the
Bible, a wooden cross, a picture of the Virgin Mary of Guadalupe, a photo of Kaaba, a prayer
rug, the Koran, and various figures of Ganesha, Shiva and Krishna (Life of Pi, 60–2).
    26
       Cf. also Randy Boyagoda’s view of the novel’s religious message (70).
286                                   JOANNA KLARA TESKE

be read in two ways: either each survival story corresponds to one religion,
or “the story with animals” corresponds to faith, while “the story without
animals” stands for agnosticism. 27 Either way the analogy implies that reli-
gions, like other beliefs, are stories.
    To sum up, the novel raises the issue of the variety of religions and their
diverse (to some extent contradictory) interpretations of God. It illustrates
the problem with Pi’s multiple religious identity and resolves the relevant
conflict in two ways. One amounts to identifying God with love as the
common denominator and crucial insight of all the religions in question and
combining devotional practices developed in each of them. The other con-
sists in interpreting religions as narrative fictions.28 Simultaneously the
novel conveys the message that theistic belief is rational, even though it may
be chosen for pragmatic or aesthetic rather than epistemic reasons.

                          5. CONTRADICTION
         BETWEEN THE STANDARD MEANING AND THE NOVEL’S USAGE
                OF THE TERMS “ATHEIST” AND “AGNOSTIC”

    The novel’s interpretation of the two attitudes is presented mainly in two
passages. In the first one, Pi notes the irrational commitment entailed in the
atheist attitude and, disregarding the content of atheistic belief, finds it close
to theism (both are faiths), whereas he disapproves of agnosticism interpret-
ed as the choice of doubt that prevents action.29 In the other passage, the
attitudes are illustrated with the imaginary scenes of the atheist’s and agno-
stic’s deaths. The former meets death with the words: “White, white! L-L-
Love! My God!”, which should be interpreted as “the deathbed leap of
faith.” Thus, the atheist is the person who may at first be sceptical but

    27
        In the light of the former interpretation, Pi’s refusal to choose one religion appears in-
consistent. After all he implores the Japanese officials to choose one story of his survival, he does
not expect them to hold both mutually exclusive accounts as true. Other reasons for preferring the
latter interpretation are presented further in the paper.
     28
        Cf. Martel’s words: “I think it’s acceptable to say that God is a fiction, if you understand
that this doesn’t necessarily mean that this fiction doesn’t exist. It just exists in a way that is only
accessed through the imagination,” (“‘The Empathetic Imagination’,” 24–5).
     29
        Cf. Pi’s words: “atheists are my brothers and sisters of a different faith, and every word
they speak speaks of faith. [. . .] It is not atheists who get stuck in my craw, but agnostics. [. . .]
To choose doubt as a philosophy of life is akin to choosing immobility as a means of trans-
portation” (37–8).
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                     287

eventually admits God’s existence. By contrast, the agnostic, “if he stays
true to his reasonable self,” will explain “the warm light bathing him” in
terms of “[p]ossibly a f-f-failing oxygenation of the b-b-brain.” As the nar-
rator explains, he “lack[s] imagination and miss[es] the better story” (85).30
In other words, the agnostic is deficient in imagination and stubborn in
his/her desire to find natural explanations to all mysteries.
    Meanwhile the standard meaning of “atheist” is “[o]ne who denies or
disbelieves the existence of God” (“Atheist”), whereas “agnostic” means
“[o]ne who holds that the existence of anything beyond and behind material
phenomena is unknown and (so far as can be judged) unknowable, and espe-
cially that a First Cause and an unseen world are subjects of which we know
nothing” (“Agnostic”).31 Thus, the atheist is not normally taken to have
a strong (irrational) belief (“faith”) that there is no God and the agnostic is
not normally taken to be a passive, unimaginative materialist.
    By re-interpreting and deprecating agnosticism (and atheism) the novel
seems to express its disapproval of rational scepticism in the matters of
religion, but doing so, the book contradicts the standard usage of the terms.
Also this contradiction is not resolved in the book.

                    6. THE THEMATIC INCONGRUITY:
          THE THEME OF GOD AND THE THEME OF NATURAL LIFE,
           WHICH IMPLY THE TENSION BETWEEN THE RELIGIOUS
                  AND NATURALIST VIEWS OF LIFE OR,
         AS STEPHENS PUTS IT, BETWEEN RELIGION AND SCIENCE32

   The thematic duality, or incongruity, in itself does not deserve the term
“contradiction,” but the two themes imply two views of life, which are often

      30
         Pi’s words that the agnostic “miss[es] the better story” provide additional evidence in
favour of reading theism (possibly also atheism) as “the better story” and neglecting the distinc-
tions between religions.
      31
         More common definitions of the agnostic do not include the materialistic implication of the
OED definition, stating only that the agnostic on the assumption that no rational judgment can be
made as regards God’s existence or non-existence for lack of relevant conclusive evidence,
suspends his/her judgment (cf. e.g. Alvin Plantinga 223).
      32
         Cf. also Cockeram’s interpretation of this conflict: “This tension between reason, logic, and
argument, on one hand, and simple religious faith and the desire to love God, on the other hand,
lies at the novel’s core. The human capacity for reason is contrasted to religious faith repeatedly
[. . .].”
288                                      JOANNA KLARA TESKE

considered contrastive. The novel is partly about God and matters of religion
(cf. Pi’s religious experience) and partly about natural life (cf. the zoo, the
shipwreck, and the island episodes).33 This apparent incongruity is resolved
by means of 1) scenes which are related to both themes, 2) analogies be-
tween certain religious and naturalistic aspects of life implied in the text or
indicated by the narrator, 3) the novel’s use of symbols uniting both themes,
4) the novel’s use of natural life as allegory for religious experience. Thus,
the two themes (God and natural life) meet, for example, in the scene in
which Pi’s biology teacher comes to the zoo and tells the boy that there is no
God. The passage on zoomorphism can serve as an example of a relevant
analogy: Pi explains that some animals (vipers in the zoo) may treat another
animal (a mouse) as one of their own kind because their needs of com-
panionship and care are stronger than the bare fact that the animal does not
resemble their own species; they can choose to act upon a fiction when this
fiction makes their life easier (112–4). Their behaviour may be interpreted as
analogous to the behaviour of religious people since in terms of the novel
religion, as suggested above, has the status of fiction.34 This analogy is not
explicit; others are less discreet. 35 The novel’s symbols indicating the possi-
bility of a reconciliation of faith and science include: Pi’s name, 36 his mind-
set reflected in his choice of studies, 37 or his encounter with the two Mr
Kumars, who teach Pi biology and Islam.38 As regards the novel’s use of
allegory, it lies at the centre of the novel: the two versions of Pi’s story may

    33
       The shipwreck story as such and the theme of religiosity are closely related if one reads Pi’s
experience as a test of his piety (like the biblical Job, Pi is exposed to extreme suffering), cf. Ines (25–6).
    34
       Cf. Pi’s comment: “I’m sure even the adult viper, as it swallowed the mouse, must have felt
somewhere in its undeveloped mind a twinge of regret, a feeling that something greater was just
missed, an imaginative leap away from the lonely, crude reality of a reptile” (114). Pi uses here
the words “leap” and “miss”, which he also uses when discussing the attitude of the atheist and
the agnostic (37, 85). The agnostic who “lack[s] imagination” cannot make “the leap of faith” and
thus “miss[es] the better story,” all he has is “dry, yeastless factuality” (85), comparable perhaps
to the “crude reality of a reptile.”
    35
       Cf. “I have heard nearly as much nonsense about zoos as I have about God and religion”
(19), or “[. . .] zoos are no longer in people’s good graces. Religion faces the same problem.
Certain illusions about freedom plague them both” (25).
    36
       Cf. Pi’s belief that his name combines science with irrationality (32).
    37
       Pi’s majors were religious studies and zoology: “the cosmogony theory of Isaac Luria, the
great sixteenth-century Kabbalist” and “a functional analysis of the thyroid gland of the three-
toed sloth” (3; cf. Stephens, 44, 48; Stephens quotes in this context a passage in which Pi
ironically compares God to a sloth, 50).
    38
       Cf. Stephens (48). The critic argues that the ship called “Tsimtsum” is yet another element
connecting in the novel science with religion (50).
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                      289

be taken to represent either different beliefs about God, or faith and agno-
sticism. The apparent incongruity in the novel’s thematic content gets re-
solved; indeed, it turns out to be part of the book’s intricate design.
    Whether this solves the tension between the religious and naturalistic
views of life seems doubtful.39 The novel clearly defends the view that
theistic belief is rational, which weakens the opposition in question, but at
the same time it tendentiously presents the factual, sceptical approach of
science as inferior to the imaginative, meaningful and uplifting faith.40

                            7. CONTRADICTION
                  BETWEEN THE FICTIONAL, QUASI-FACTUAL
                AND METAFICTIONAL MODES OF PRESENTATION

    The novel is formally incoherent as it incorporates semi-documentary,
openly fictional (at times almost fantastic41) and metafictional passages. The
semi-documentary character of the novel is created by the “Author’s Note,”
in which the “author” explains how he has come to know the story of Pi
Patel, by the “author’s” words of gratitude directed among others at Mr Patel
and the Canada Council for the Arts (a real institution which lends the
fictional character an air of reality); by the words of gratitude spoken by Pi
at the end of his story, and by the attached semi-documents: the transcript of
the conversation and the report. By contrast, the title, Life of Pi: A Novel, the
usual generic features of the novel (e.g. the style, division into chapters) as
well as the story itself make it clear that the book is a work of fiction.
Finally, the metafictional elements include the discussion of fiction (x),42 the
round number of chapters together with Pi’s reflection upon it (383, as
a character in the story Pi should be unaware of such issues), Pi’s theory that
all knowledge (all representation of reality) is to some extent fictional and
narrative in character, or the intertextual names of the ship and the tiger.

    39
        Cf. Stephens, who argues that the book tries to reconcile the domains of science and
religion (both are valuable, partly narrative and complementary to each other), yet in their place
recommends imaginative narrative, also as a way to faith and redemption.
    40
        Cf. Werner Wolf’s belief that the novel contrasts the religious with the secular and
rationalist view of life to recommend the former (qtd in Maria Stefanescu 55–8).
    41
       Jerry Coyne describes the book as a “fantasy tale” and a “powerful piece of magic realism” (575).
    42
       The “author” suggests there that fiction should be taken as “selective transforming of
reality” that aims to bring out its essence.
290                                   JOANNA KLARA TESKE

   This formal incongruity (fictional, factual and metafictional passages)
when translated into propositions takes the shape of contradiction: “the story
of Pi’s life is fiction” (p) and “the story of Pi’s life is not fiction” (~p). The
conflict between fictional and factual narratives seems annulled by Pi’s con-
tention that all that we take as non-fiction is in fact partly fiction. As regards
metafiction, it aims, according to Patricia Waugh, to question the notions of
reality and fiction (2); one might therefore argue that it is used in the novel to
emphasize the theme of the partial fictionality of all representations of reality.
The discord present on the level of techniques may be said to be resolved on
the thematic level, where the fictional, factual and metafictional elements
work together to subvert the traditional distinction between facts and fiction.43

                     8. FRAGMENTATION OF THE NOVEL
                AND THE CONSEQUENT SENSE OF INCONGRUITY

    The novel not only employs various narrative modes, but is also frag-
mented in its construction. It consists of a dedication (“à mes parents et
à mon frère,” which sounds like Pi addressing the family that he has lost),
the “Author’s Note,” three parts and 100 chapters. In part one two narrative
situations are intertwined: the story of Pi’s childhood and shipwreck is
printed in the standard font, while the story of the “author’s” present-day
encounter with Pi is italicised. To make matters more confusing Pi’s identity
is not explicitly revealed in these passages so that only with time does the
reader realize that the aging man living with his family in Canada is Pi. Part
two tells the story of the shipwreck. Part three opens with an italicized com-
ment on the remaining contents of the book: a transcript of a tape-recorded
conversation and a report of the investigation of the sunken ship. This con-
struction is worth noting, even though it exemplifies a lack of integrity, not
contradiction, because it demands of the reader the use of the coherence
principle. The reader who assumes that the text is intelligible has to collect
all the elements, decide on their priority and mutual relations. Eventually all
these elements make sense: they are related to Pi’s life and contribute to the
novel’s religious-epistemological theme.

     43
        Also, since metafiction undermines the reader’s suspension of disbelief, the metafictional ele-
ment in the book contributes to the novel’s experimental testing of the reader’s willingness to believe
(like the overtly fantastic elements, metafiction discourages the reader from believing the story).
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                      291

                                         CONCLUSION

    As regards epistemology, the novel indicates that it is rational to assume
that all beliefs contain fictional and narrative elements, as well as that un-
verifiable beliefs which do not contradict facts, even if they do not explain
much, in the absence of epistemically more satisfactory beliefs, may ratio-
nally be accepted if this brings practical benefits. The novel then applies this
theory to religious experience to suggest that in the absence of conclusive
evidence proving or disproving God’s existence, theism is the advisable
choice. Faith demands some imagination and effort of will, but it rewards the
believer with the ability to love and a sense of being loved. The choice of
faith is not irrational even if it is made on pragmatic rather than epistemic
grounds.44 The novel offers both an experiment and arguments to convey this
message. 45
    Even so, the message seems open to questioning, as I have already sug-
gested while discussing the novel’s account of human knowledge, epistemic
criteria, agnosticism and the relation between science and faith. Without re-
peating the details, one may note in conclusion that epistemic scepticism is
comprehensible with reference to Transcendence but much less so when
empirical reality is involved – the novel does not seem to note the dif-
ference. Further, the praise of the richness of imaginative life and benefits of
stories that promote love, associated with religion,46 goes in the novel to-
gether with a disapproval of the poverty of scepticism and cognitive
backwardness, associated with science—this view of science seems biased.
    The novel’s method is not beyond criticism either. The aesthetic ex-
perience offered by Life of Pi can be analyzed in terms of experiment and

    44
        Cf. also Thorpe (51). It is worth noting that Pi insists that he is “reasonable”; he only
objects to being “excessively reasonable” as this may impoverish life (400). Pi also respects facts
(cf. the experiment with the bananas in the sink filled with water, 393–5).
     45
        Cf. also Martel’s statement: “Religion [. . .] makes you suspend your disbelief so that fac-
tual truth becomes irrelevant. It's not because facts are ignored. It’s more how you interpret the
facts [. . .]” (24). Martel explains further that faith does not dispense with reason, but interpreting
facts, takes advantage of imagination; it is a mistake to overestimate reason (“’The Empathetic
Imagination’” 25–7).
     46
        Nota bene, recommending theistic belief on pragmatic grounds, the novel fails to consider
possible unintended side-effects of this belief. It may help people live, but it may also prove
dangerous (cf. religious persecutions, fanatical suicides, etc). Even if the risk may be minimized
in the kind of pragmatic, rational religiosity recommended by the novel, it still seems worth
considering.
292                                  JOANNA KLARA TESKE

manipulation. The readers are offered an opportunity to see how much they
can believe if a vision of a morally/emotionally acceptable world is at stake.
They are also challenged to reconsider the criteria which help them choose
one version of the story out of the two conflicting possibilities. Finally, they
are encouraged to think to what extent their conclusions might apply to other
spheres of life, other beliefs they hold, in particular, those related to their
religious experience. I shall call this the experimental aspect of the book; it
seems precious and uncontroversial.
    The other aspect, constituted by the implied author’s interpretation of the
experiment, seems more problematic as the readers may feel manipulated
into accepting this interpretation.47 The novel first stages the fictional rea-
lity, appeals to the readers’ emotions, engages them in an experiment and
asks important questions. Then, making use of allegory, with much authority
(Pi and the “author” both seem to act as the implied author’s mouthpieces)
the novel offers its own interpretation of the experiment. I have argued
above that this interpretation seems in certain respects mistaken or biased,
but even critical and attentive readers at this stage may welcome it with
relief. They have been told a long and tragic story, their credulity has been
tested, now at last everything makes sense and they can enjoy a happy end-
ing (choose the “story with animals”), provided that they accept the novel’s
allegedly rational epistemology. The author seems confident that the reader
should be satisfied.48 The pressure may be hard to resist.
    Some risk seems part of all aesthetic experience. If readers decline to
suspend their disbelief and get involved, they lose a chance to gain new
insights. To minimize the risk of manipulation contemporary art often lays
bare its own artefactual character, proclaims the artist’s lack of authority.
Even though it employs metafiction, Life of Pi seems unaware of the risk, or
perhaps implying that life is a story, the novel cannot issue the relevant
warning without contradicting itself.
    As regards contradictions, it appears that the novel 1) offers the readers a
chance to test their willingness to ignore contradictions, 2) explicitly proble-
matizes the theme of contradictions and their role in cognition (e.g.

   47
       Cf. Stefanescu’s analysis of the novel’s strategy of persuasion (57).
   48
       Cf. Boyagoda’s description of the authorial message: “Of course Martel wants us to believe
in Pi’s original version [. . .]. In his view, to do so is a leap of faith, which in turn is a leap
towards God: the God brought into existence by the novel itself, a strange mishmash of religious
notions and figures that together comprise the deity that Pi creates and celebrates. In short, a God
of fiction” (71).
LIFE OF PI BY YANN MARTEL                                  293

questioning the value of the criterion of believability based on consistence of
beliefs), 3) for full appreciation demands that the reader be attentive both to
textual contradictions (trying to integrate various conflicting elements of the
text in the name of the principle of coherence) and, sometimes deceptive,
coherences (in need of the reader’s critical examination).

                                       BIBLIOGRAPHY

“Agnostic.” Def. A. Oxford English Dictionary. 2nd ed. 1989.
 “Atheist.” Def. A.1. Oxford English Dictionary. 2nd ed. 1989.
Boyagoda, Randy. “Faith, Fiction, Flotsam.” Rev. of Life of Pi, by Yann Martel. First Things:
    A Monthly Journal of Religion & Public Life 133 (2003): 69–72.
Cockeram, Paul. “Life of Pi”. Masterplots. Salem Press, 2010. Literary Reference Center Plus.
    Ebsco. Web 05.11.2013.
Coyne, Jerry, A. Rev. of Life of Pi, by Yann Martel. Nature 460 (2009): 575.
Dwyer, June. “Yann Martel's Life of Pi and the Evolution of the Shipwreck Narrative.” Modern
    Language Studies 35.2 (2005): 9–21.
Ines, Charlotte. “Robinson Crusoe, Move Over.” Rev. of Life of Pi, by Yann Martel. The Nation
    275.6 (2002): 25–9.
Ketterer, David. “Yann Martel’s Life of Pi and Poe’s Pym (and ‘Berenice’).” Poe Studies/Dark
    Romanticism: History, Theory, Interpretation (PoeS) 42 (2009): 80–6.
Martel, Yann. “‘The Empathetic Imagination’: An Interview with Yann Martel.” Interview by
    Sabine Sielke. Canadian Literature 177 (2003): 12–23.
Martel, Yann. Life of Pi: A Novel. Edinburgh: Canongate, 2003.
Plantinga, Alvin. “Agnosticism.” A Companion to Epistemology. 2nd ed. Eds. Jonathan Dancy,
    Ernest Sosa, Matthias Steup. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010.
Skidelsky, William. “Novel Thoughts.” New Statesman 131.4598 (2002): 39.
Stefanescu, Maria. “Revisiting the Implied Author Yet Again: Why (Still) Bother?” Style 45:1
    (2011): 48-66.
Stephens, Gregory. “Feeding Tiger, Finding God: Science, Religion, and ‘the Better Story’ in Life
    of Pi.” Intertexts 14.1 (2010): 41–59.
Thorpe, Brian. Rev. of Life of Pi, by Yann Martel. Touchstone 21.1 (2003): 51–4.
Waugh, Patricia. Metafiction: The Theory and Practice of Self-Conscious Fiction. London:
    Methuen, 1985.
Ziolkowski, Eric. “Religion, Literature, and the Climate of Fear: Intimations of a Polynomous
    Culture.” World Literature Today 82.2 (2008): 38–42.

                         ŻYCIE PI YANNA MARTELA —
             UŻYCIE SPRZECZNOŚCI W EKSPERYMENTALNEJ POWIEŚCI
            NA TEMAT EPISTEMOLOGICZNEGO STATUSU WIARY W BOGA
                                       Streszczenie
   Artykuł omawia Życie Pi Yanna Martela, koncentrując się na sposobach, w jaki powieść wy-
korzystuje sprzeczności, by poruszyć temat teistycznych, ateistycznych i agnostycznych prze-
konań. Powieść zdaje się bronić tezy, że teizm jest racjonalny (ze względu raczej na pragma-
294                                JOANNA KLARA TESKE

tyczne niż epistemiczne racje), ateizm swym zaangażowaniem przypomina wiarę, podczas gdy
agnostycyzm można utożsamić z dogmatycznym materializmem i biernym podejściem do życia.
By zilustrować ten punkt widzenia, powieść proponuje czytelnikowi eksperyment, przedstawiając
mu dwie wzajemnie sprzeczne wersje historii ocalenia Pi.
                                                              Streściła Joanna Klara Teske

Słowa kluczowe: Życie Pi, Yann Martel, sprzeczności, wiara, poznanie.
You can also read