The Compassion of Orthodoxy: The Prometheus Bound of Aeschylus

Page created by Lillian Fernandez
 
CONTINUE READING
A Zeus wronged by Prometheus and an
                                                Aeschylus wronged by the critics

  The Compassion of Orthodoxy:
The Prometheus Bound of Aeschylus
                             Robert L. Houbeck, Jr.

ONE    OF THE central interpretative dif-       of Prometheus, as savage, arbitrary, even
ficulties with the Prometheus Bound of          ~njust.~
Aeschylus has been to account for the              Surely Prometheus sees Zeus as a cruel
poet’s seemingly uncharacteristic treat-        and high-handed tyrant. So too have most
ment of Zeus. The problem for the critics       critics seen him. Yet, was this the poet’s
has been simply that the Zeus of the Pro-       view of the Zeus of his Prometheus
metheus Bound does not seem very                Bound! With whom do the poet’s sym-
Zeuslike. The poet has portrayed him as         pathies truly lie: with Prometheus or with
brutal, vengeful, insecure-not at all the       Zeus? The answer is incontestable. The
far-seeing, wise Father-Zeus of Hesiod or       Zeus of the Prometheus Bound is not a
the other surviving plays of the Aeschy-        brutal and arbitrary despot, but is in fact
lean corpus.                                    the same protector of the unseen measure
  Most commentators have sought to              of Dike, of justice, that Aeschylus depicted
resolve this seeming anomaly in                 in his other dramas. Prometheus, as
Aeschylus’s treatment of Zeus by sug-           Aeschylus portrayed him, is not a victim,
gesting that, over the course of the trilogy,   but a justly punished transgressor of the
Zeus would “evolve” into a mellower dei-        divine order.
ty.’ Others have brusquely cut through the        This view nas seemed incredible to
knot by positing a Zeus who, rather than        some critics. Podlecki mentions the no-
change his character, would simply              tion, but dismisses it almost contemp-
change his mind. They construct a Zeus          tuously.6 Lloyd-Jones finds it “an opinion
who will “do a deal” with Prometheus;2 or       that has gone out of fashion in this cen-
a Realpolitiker Zeus, a sort of Attic                                        ~ a careful if un-
                                                tury, and no w ~ n d e r . ”Yet,
Bismarck, who will strike a power-political     fashionable reading of the play will reveal
bargain with the rebellious Titan3 Others       that the poet’s sympathies lie not with Pro-
wonder whether Aeschylus really wrote           metheus but with Zeus. The “problem of
the play after alL4 What the majority of        Zeus” is a problem only for critics who
the play’s modern critics do agree upon,        have read literally what Aeschylus has
however, is this: The Zeus of this play is      meant ironically.
different from the traditional Zeus. The          This interpretation of the play is neither
poet has portrayed him, in his punishment       perverse nor unique, though a reading of

Modern Age                                                                                 33
                              LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
                       ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
the critics, where they mention it at all,     vik plausibly suggests,” this was a
would incline one so to think. Nicolaus        tempered generation. They were nat the
Wecklein formulated the view well in           progress-fattened, increasingly bellicose
1897:                                          Athenians of the later fifth century. They
   The whole plot of the drama turns on        were not possessed of a sense of skep-
   the character of Prometheus. By his ex-     ticism about the gods. They had ex-
   ample it is shown that every revolt         perienced, and recently, their providence
   against Zeus must necessarily come          in the Persian wars. They would have
   from ignorance of his wise designs, that    been particularly grateful in recollecting
   every fault imputed to him has its foun-    that providence. These men had seen, too,
   dations in a purblind and malicious         the ambiguous benefits of that fire which
   judgment, and that any seeming              was Prometheus’s special gift to mankind,
   ground for insubordination, however         fire which indeed warms the hearth, but
   specious and seductive, must in the end     also forges the weapons that slay com-
   prove a snare and a delusion.8              rades and razes the homes that shelter
                                               loved ones. We may well wonder with
Zeus in the Prometheus Bound of Aeschy-        what unalloyed enthusiasm such a pious
lus is not a despot; he is a father. Pro-      and annealed generation would have
metheus is not a rebel to be admired; he is    entertained such a gift and its larcenous
a rebel to be punished and, perhaps,           giver: “benefactor,” indeed, who gave
through punishment, made to see the er-        men fire but not also the sophrosyne, the
ror of his pride and the justice of his        wisdom and due measure necessary to use
bonds.                                         that gift well.
   A handful of other commentators have           ‘To be sure, we know nothing about the
also argued this position: Eirik Vandvik, in   criteria the archon might have applied
a 1942 monograph, and, more briefly, Eric      when approving plays for production. Nor
Voegelin (1957, 1968) and Leo Strauss          can we be sure precisely how audiences
(1968).9Yet, a student perusing the critical   reacted to this particular play (or to any
literature will scarcely find these commen-    play of the early fifth century). But it is im-
tators cited, even in bibliographies. More     plausible to suppose, as both Wecklein and
important, he will virtually never find the    Vandvik point out, that a play which truly
position they argue examined and con-          portrayed Zeus as a cruel tyrant (especial-
futed. This silence is a puzzle.               ly if that play were the first play of a
   As Eric Voegelin once observed, the         trilogy, as the “evolutionary-Zeus’’ critics
stream is clearest at its source. Let us try   are constrained to argue12) would have
to get behind the secular, romantic con-       been t01erated.I~ We do know that
notations that have encrusted the figure of    Aeschylus was an unusually respected
Prometheus and re-examine ,the play that       citizen and that his plays were accorded
Aeschylus, not Shelley or Coethe, actually     the unusual honor of being re-produced (at
wrote. What we will find is a Zeus             a time, perhaps, when some thought his
wronged by Prometheus and an Aeschy-           dramas might fortify an increasingly deca-
lus wronged by the critics.                    dent p ~ p u l a c e ) In
                                                                      . ~ sum,
                                                                          ~    the Prometheus
                     I1                        trilogy, or any other play produced at that
                                               time for that audience, could not have por-
Many in the audience that attended the         trayed Zeus in any but the traditional
Prometheus trilogy, first performed at          Hesiodic light, as far-seeing, wise Father-
Athens perhaps as early as 479-.78 B.C.,l0     Zeus, at once stern and gentle, who
would have been men of the generation of        establishes and ensures justice, but a Zeus
Marathon, men who were, like the poet           also possessed of a “mind unknowable for
himself, “Marathon champions,” men who          men.”15 And this latter is the key point. As
had seen war and experienced the                all Athenians knew from Hesiod, Pro-
“miracle” of the Creek victory. As Vand-        metheus had sought to deceive Zeus at

34                                                                              Winter 1986
                      LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
               ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
Mekone, but “Zeus, full of eternal counsel,      An Athenian audience, though, mindful
 saw through the stratagem and noted it        of the cruel excesses of genuine tyrants
 we11.”’6 Through the rage of the im-          like the HippiasZ0of their fathers’ genera-
 moderate Prometheus the Athenian au-          tion or the contemporary Hiero at
 dience could read the true face of Father-    Syracuse, could understand how absurd
 Zeus. Children cannot always com-             and even self-damning such a description
 prehend the wisdom of a father, especially    of the wise and mighty son of Kronos must
 when he is teaching them hard lessons.        be. In Prometheus’s prideful and distorted
 How easily they misconstrue his actions       accusations that audience would im-
 and his intent. His ways often seem alien     mediately sense disorder. They would see
 and excessively hard. But mature men can      the irony in these descriptions of Zeus as
 recognize the directing heart behind the      cruel and arbitrary tyrant: Zeus, who
firm hand. They recognize the gift of in-      overthrew a genuine tyrant, the
struction, the need for them to learn cer-     murderous Kronos, swallower of his own
tain things, if not through obedience, then    children; Zeus, who established in place of
 through suffering.                            the ancient chaos, not a new tyranny, but
   To modern critics the gods may be mere      the order of Dike,an order mirrored in the
literary figures. We are tempted to read       lawfulness and security of the polis. An
them automatically, when we encounter          Athenian audience, though not all modern
them in myth or drama, as symbols for          critics, could distinguish between the
man. But to fifth-century Athenians the        ironic voice of Aeschylus, the playwright,
gods were living realities. One might steal    and the deluded voice of Prometheus, the
from one’s neighbor and the gods look the      punished.
other way. But only a madman - or a               Finally, again from the point of view of
mad god - would steal from the hearth of       that early fifth-century Athenian au-
Zeus.I7 An Athenian spectator, though not      dience, consider the disparity between the
a modern critic, would take seriously that     Prometheus portrayed on the stage - de-
he was watching a play about the gods.         fiant rebel, self-declared enemy of Zeus
How that spectator must have shuddered         who considers himself an unjustly
to hear even another god, let alone a man,     persecuted “coordinate power” - and the
call himself - as early on in the-play         Prometheus that audience knew well. The
(1. 120)1*- the enemy of Zeus! How chill-      audience knew the altar to Prometheus in
ing to hear Prometheus’s outburst, “In a       the Academy. They knew the torch-race
word, I hate all the gods!” (1. 975.) And      run each year in his honor. They knew
how that spectator might have nodded in        him as a deity, though a minor deity.21He
agreement with Hermes’ quietly precise         was the god of potters and craftsmen. He
diagnosis of that outburst: “It appears you    was not, in the fifth-century Athenian pan-
have been stricken with no small               theon, in any sense a rival of Zeus. That he
madness.” (1. 977.) Such a spectator might     may have once so imagined himself must
admire Prometheus’s courage, his en-           have been, to a contemporary audience, a
durance of pain, might even sympathize         striking example of self-delusion. More-
with his unfortunate plight; but it is ex-     over, if Prometheus once did imagine
ceedingly dubious that any sensible            himself a serious competitor with Zeus for
Greek, though not necessarily every            honor, an Athenian audience would ex-
modern critic, would fail to understand        pect the poet to explain, not merely how
precisely where justice lay between Zeus       the Titan came to be released by Zeus, but
and Prometheus. Prometheus had directly        how he came to be reconciled with Zeus,
violated the order established by Zeus.        how he came to recognize his own delu-
The Titan and even Zeus’s own rather           sion and to accept Zeus’s position - and
slow-witted henchmen, Strength and             his own - as just and ordinate. Deals and
Violence,lg might characterize Zeus’s rule     bargains are not the stuff of reconcilia-
as that of a “tyrant.”                         tions.

Modern Age                                                                              35
                              LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
                       ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
Ill                        seems to regard it, as a tyrant’s allocation
                                               of the booty, where Prometheus feels
Still, such external evidence is only cir-     himself to have been “shorted”? Or was it
cumstantial. What evidence is there within     perhaps in truth something nobler and
the play to suggest that Prometheus,           subtler: the establishment of order
though the central character of the drama,     through the apportioning of that which
is not intended by the playwright to be        was due each in justice? In either case,
seen as an admirable character?                Prometheus does not say what place he
   The first thing to notice is the most ob-   was given - perhaps a place not high
vious of all: Prometheus is a prisoner. He     enough for one of his intelligence and
is being punished. Now some punishments        foresight? He then defied the will of Zeus
are justified, some are not. We do not         and somehow “protected’ the race of men
know at the beginning of the play (at least    from being destroyed by Zeus, who had
those of us for whom the first play of the     intended to create in their place another
trilogy has been lost) whether this punish-    race of men. With what was Zeus
ment is justified or unjustified. But we do    dissatisfied in the present race of men that
know that the testimony of a prisoner          he intended to create them anew? And
against his jailer will not necessarily be     with what new characteristics would they
dispassionate. When Prometheus calls           be endowed? Prometheus does not say.
Zeus brutal and ungrateful, we ought not       Nor does he specify how he managed to
to be too ready to believe him without         preserve the race of men from the god
evidence. It is precisely here, in for-        who had just subdued the race of Titans.
mulating their evaluation of the character     Prometheus, we observe, had not been
of Zeus on the basis of the testimony of a     able to preserve himself.
pinioned opponent, that many critics                 Prometheus continues, boasting to the
become astonishingly docile. They believe      chorus, ‘‘I dared” (I. 236), and seems
the prisoner.22                                pleased with the pity his plight arouses in
   Yet as we observe the character of Pro-     the chorus. But Prometheus has not been
metheus closely, as the poet develops it,      totally candid. The chorus senses that he
for example, in the exchanges with the         has omitted something from his account.
chorus of Oceanids, we notice unsettling       “Did your offense perhaps go further than
traits. We learn that Prometheus, when he      you have said?” “Yes, I caused men no
was unable to persuade the other Titans to     longer to foresee their death.” (11. 248-49.)
use guile to defeat Zeus, went over to         He gave men blind hopefulness. It was
Zeus’s party in order to be on the winning     a strange gift, one reflects, to obscure
side. His Titan kin were severely punished     from mortals their essential mortality. Pro-
by the victorious Zeus. Prometheus now         metheus then volunteers yet more infor-
complains when he, having in turn               mation. “I did more than that: I gave them-
betrayed Zeus as he had his fellow Titans,      fire.” (1. 253.) This revelation shocks the
is similarly punished. In one of Aeschylus’s   chorus. “What? Men, whose life is but a
additions to Hesiods account, Prometheus       day, possess already the hot radiance of
claims that it was his counsel that had        fire? . . . This then was the offense for
given Zeus victory. We note, though, that      which you suffer. . . . Oh, you were wrong
he does not say precisely what that            - do you not see?” (11. 254,256, 260.) Pro-
counsel was. Does he mean that Zeus had         metheus then petulantly, turns upon the
been without sufficient cunning to defeat      Oceanids: “Oh, it is easy for you who are
the dull Titans? Prometheus tells the           free to give advice. ‘Wrong?’ 1 accept the
chorus that when Zeus finally gained vic-       word. I willed, willed to be wrong! . . . Yet
tory he “at once appointed various rights       I did not expect such punishment as this.”
to various gods, giving to each his set         (11. 263-68.) H e exults in his willfulness. He-
place and authority.” (1. 232.) Ought this      is also, surprisingly, surprised at his
apportioning to be seen, as Prometheus          deserts.

36                                                                               Winter 1986
                      LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
               ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
The poet, in a short space, reveals this     about him only through others. He never
suffering god to be ambitious, a little         appears, yet his presence broods over the
dense, and not entirely open in admitting       play - not at all unlike, one might sup-
the nature of his trespass. We wonder           pose, the all-seeing sun whom the Titan in-
what sort of plan Prometheus may have           voked in that opening monologue, who
thwarted, what sort of race of men Zeus         “looks upon his suffering.” Nor is the idea
may have been intending to bring forth          on the face of it absurd that far-seeing
before the theft: a race perhaps less in-       Zeus is looking on. With what motive? To
clined to misuse the gift of fire because       sate his lust for vengeance? Perhaps. But
wiser and more measured; perhaps, in            what if Zeus were in fact allowing events
fact, a race of men more like the virtuous      to take this course for another reason?
and just Heracles, whose father was Zeus        What if he had foreseen and permitted
and whose great-grandmother was lo,             Prometheus’s deception, permitted his de-
whose fate Prometheus misconstrues as           fiance, permitted his gift of fire? What if
mi~fortune.‘~  Prometheus, the proud fore-      Zeus were allowing events to trip along,
thinker, seems not to have foreseen the         seemingly out of his control? After all, it
mixed consequences for man of his “gifts.”      was Zeus who had commanded that Pro-
Even the rather flighty Oceanids see            metheus be bound far from the company
something disturbing and even horrifying        of gods and men. Yet, apart from his brief
in the gift of fire to “creatures of a day.”    opening monologue, Prometheus is never
And why does he who can discern the             alone. He is visited by Oceanids, by
future seem surprised and irritated by the      Oceanus, by Io, by Hermes. All have
chorus’s admonitions? Did he not foresee        something to say to him about repent-
their reaction, even as he did not foresee      ance. Even Hephaestus, though pitying
the punishment Zeus would visit upon            him, admonishes him that he has trans-
him? Frankly, we soon begin to wonder           gressed. Yet Prometheus is not disposed to
how stable and reliable are the claims of,      hear these counselors whom Zeus, if not
as Wecklein describes him, this “short-         provides, then certainly allows.
sighted Forethinker.” What of his                 Consider, too, the seemingly minor mat-
testimony can-we believe? Perhaps the           ter of the location of his punishment. Zeus
loyal Strength was not being cruelly taunt-     has ordered that Prometheus be isolated
ing but simply direct when he left the          from the community of the gods. Yet he
newly bound Prometheus to his suffering:        also apparently permits a whole battalion
“You’re wrongly named, Prometheus,              of characters to troop across a desolate
Wise-before-the-event! Wisdom is just the       beach giving him advice. The Titan’s reac-
thing you want.” (1. 86.)                       tion to this parade is revealing. It does not
   Reflecting on these curiosities, we begin    occur to him that Zeus must certaiiily be
to suspect that the poet had, from Pro-         permitting these visitations to go on. He
metheus’s opening monologue, begun to           does not consider to what end. Rather, he
hint at the Titan’s instability of character.   condemns Zeus for the humiliation of such
Conacher points out clearly, but without        a public punishment. “Would that Zeus
suggesting their possible significance, the     had sent me under the earth.. . . Instead
rapid fluctuations of mood Prometheus           ... my torments bring joy to my
displays in his opening lines (11. 88-10 I),    enemies.” (11. 152-59.)This particular place
from restraint through passion to self-         of punishment, on the contrary, has been
rebuke.24 Through this indirection, the         arranged by Zeus as an opportunity for
poet powerfully suggests that this god is       Prometheus to “focus his mind,” as Dr.
indeed erratic and disoriented, a prisoner      Johnson might have described it, yet to
not only of Zeus but also of his passions.      focus it apart from a scorning multitude. In
  Unsettled by these oddities in the por-       this place the Titan might learn the mean-
trayal of Prometheus, we may then begin         ing of his crime, through suffering, yes,
to wonder about this Zeus. We know              but also through counsel by sympathetic

Modern Age                                                                                37
                              LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
                       ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
creatures for whom Tartarus would have         shall prove true.” (11. 928-29.) His state-
been inaccessible. Until a punishment is       ment is not conditional.
seen by the one punished as being just and       Increasingly Prometheus appears a
deserved, then resentment gnaws, as ef-        short-sighted, impetuous, albeit generous-
fectively as an eagle gnawing at a liver -     hearted boaster. We see everywhere the
the locus of the passions - and one will       ironic hand of the playwright. With uner-
not repent. Rather, any punishment will        ring precision, Aeschylus has selected his
then seem outrageous and unjust. Zeus          protagonist for this theme of rebellion
was not seeking the “secret” that Pro-         against the divine order: a Titan. Kerenyi
metheus thought he could use against the       reminds us of Hesiod’s words about this
god, nor was he seeking vengeance; he          race:
was seeking repentance and with it
                                                  Father Ouranos had given them (the
restoration of the disrupted order within
                                                  race of Iapetos, the father of Pro-
the community of gods and men. But Pro-
                                                  metheus) the name “Titans” as a term
metheus, prisoner of his passions more
                                                  of abuse and as a pun, as if the word
than of Zeus, could not see in his situation
                                                  were derived from titainein, “to over-
the directing hand of the god.
                                                  reach oneself,” and from tisis, “punish-
   How, exactly, one wonders, ought Zeus          ment”: the Titans had “over-reached’
to have reacted toward this god who hates         themselves, in their foolhardiness, by
the gods? He did with him what one does           attempting to perform a great work,
with those who defy the law: separate him         and for this they were later punished.25
from the community and punish him. Pro-
metheus was clearly neither powerful              As the play proceeds, Prometheus ap-
enough nor clever enough nor far-sighted       pears less wise rather than more noble,
enough to elude him. He reveals himself        stubborn rather than forebearing. His
to be a most “ungodly” sort of god: con-       catalogue of the gifts he has given to man,
sumed with anger and resentment for the        for instance, bears examination in this
god who will not give him what he insists      light. His gifts are not exclusively
is his due. He rages, but he is powerless.     materialistic. Rather, they are useful, prac-
He boasts of his foreknowledge, yet that       tical gifts: carpentry; arithmetic; medicine;
which he foresees that we know to be true      the harnessing of animals, especially
he has learned only through his mother,        horses; shipbuilding. These latter gifts,
Themis (1. 873), not through his own gifts.    though, are not without ambiguity. A
When he claims, concerning the secret          harnessed animal can be used to haul
consequence of Zeus’s future liaison with      water; but it can also become “an orna-
Thetis, “There is no god but I who can         ment of wealth.” (1. 468.) Shipping, too,
reveal to him [Zeus] the way to avert this     can transport timber and grain but also
ignominy [of Zeus’s fall from power            unguents and fine cloth. Both gifts would
through a son born of Thetis]. I know it       imply to a fifth-century audience the prob-
all.” (1. 915.), Prometheus has forgotten      lems attendant upon the growing wealth
that there surely is another - the woman       produced by a vigorous, disciplined peo-
from whom he learned the secret in the         ple: corrosive tendencies toward in-
first place, Themis. How much else that he     dulgence in luxuries and extravagance in
“foresees” does he know only through           consumption, both recurring concerns in
her? How much in these “foresights” are        Athenian society. Prometheus’s gifts en-
self-deluded boasts? He solemnly assures       tailed dangers, dangers to private and
Io several times that Zeus shall be de-        hence to civic virtues.
posed, which his audience knows to be un-          What sorts of gifts were left off the
true. The chorus even suspects the emp-        Titan’s list? He did not give men the polis
tiness of these assertions: “These threats     - that was the gift of Zeus. He taught men
against Zeus surely voice but your own         divination - but not the offering of due
wish.” Yet the Titan insists, “I speak what    sacrifice, not piety, not the justice of wor-

38                                                                             Winter 1986
                      LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
               ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
ship. His gifts to man reflected his own        metheus Unbound, that the Titan would
limited perspective: useful gifts but not the   come to see his delusion, to face reality
noblest. Isolated from controlling wisdom,      squarely. That reality was that he was a
a wisdom which he himself rejected, these       minor god under the order of Zeus, the
useful gifts could become, in the hands of      order of Dike. As the fragments we do
unvirtuous creatures of a day, positively       possess of that final play indicate, the van-
perverse. To rule themselves, in the polis      quished Titans have made their peace
and in the soul, but under the acknowl-         with Zeus. They have submitted to his
edged aegis of far-seeing Zeus: that was        order. Prometheus, too, will submit, not
noblest for man the creature. The highest       from exhaustion but from recognition of
gifts came from Zeus. They could be             the rightness of submission.
secured only through self-control, self-          Prometheus was great-hearted and
denial, suffering.                              courageous beyond the measure of mor-
  What precisely was Prometheus’s               tals. To call him a minor god is not to
crime? Was it ultimately this “gift” of fire    diminish much his distance from the
(which had not been his to give)? Was it        creatures he loved too well. Yet, as Leo
these unblessed blessings, whose am-            Strauss observed:
biguous consequences in some way                   The very greatness of Prometheus,
reflected their blemished origin? Voegelin         which is so powerfully exhibited in the
suggests that the theft was “only the most         play, may be meant to give us an ink-
tangible symptom of a more primordial              ling of the greatness of Zeus, of Zeus’
defiance.. . . This self-willed defiance of        wisdom. Zeus is so great that he cannot
Prometheus (see especially 1. 268) is not          be understood, that he must appear as a
the assertion of a righteous claim against         cruel tyrant, before he has manifested
despotism.” Rather, Prometheus does not            himself.28
“know himself”; he does not possess “the
reflective self-knowledge that makes one          Zeus is never seen in the play, not
aware of limitations and obligations under      primarily from a dramatic convention, but
order.” Precisely, Prometheus suffers           because Dike, justice, is never directly          ’

from an “excess of pity (1. 241) and a defi-    seen. It is the unseen measure. Yet it is
ciency in fear of God.” (1. 542.)               nonetheless real. Its fruits are visible, as
                                                are the consequences of its transgression,
   For the excess of pity distorts the sense    to those with eyes prepared to see and
   of the place of man in his relation to       ears disposed to hear.
   God, of his conditio humana: Pro-
   metheus tried to bestow honors (time)                              IV
   on man “beyond his true portion” (1.
   30), and he replaced the divine decision     The Prometheus Bound of Aeschylus is a
   with regard to the fate of man by “his       play filled with irony and surrounded by
   private opinion or decision (idia            irony. It is filled with irony because its cen-
                (1. 544.)                       tral character, Prometheus, misunderstands
  Prometheus, then, suffers from “a             and hence continuallymisinterprets his own
madness, a nosos, disease” (1. 977) that        situation; it is surrounded by ‘irony because
“can be healed only by self-conquering          the majority of modern commentators
submis~ion.”~~     (11. 999 ff.). Prometheus,   share Prometheus’s misunderstanding and
though, vows never to “kneel to my              similarly misinterpret his condition. What
detested enemy, with womanish hands             a rich, Aeschylean irony: that the deluded
outspread in supplication for release.” (11.    Prometheus has also deluded his diviners;
1001-2.)                                        that the mistake of one infects those who
  Prometheus was deluded. He thought he         come after him; that Aeschylus and Zeus
was that which he was not. It would not be      prove themselves to be in fact wiser than
until the final play of the trilogy, the Pro-   Prometheus and his creatures.

Modern Age                                                                                  39
                             LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
                      ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
The Prometheus Bound indeed treats a                Shelley. We have precisely reversed the
deeply religious theme: the consequences              symbols of disease and order.
of the revolt against the order of Zeus,                Whoever was the Alexandrian scholiast
which is the order of justice. Grief,                 who conceived the title of the play, Pro-
Aeschylus shows us, always follows from               metheus Bound, he understood well
the revolt. The unseen measure indeed                 Aeschylus’s intent. Prometheus was
rules. The play affirms that Zeus is both             bound - externally and internally. He
stern judge and wise teacher, that his                was not free because he was deluded. The
ways are, as Hesiod taught, often in-                 order of Zeus was not, as he imagined, a
scrutable but always just.                            tyranny designed to oppress him. If
  This is a strange theme to moderns, who             was not designed at all. It simply WQS.
believe neither in gods nor in an order of            What it was was the order of Dike, of
justice inscribed in the very being of                justice of the unseen measure. Aeschylus
things. Hence the inability of the age to             understood that that order was real and
fathom a pope who both embraces and ad-               that reality could never be a tyranny. To
monishes. We no longer understand the                 imagine it so is the real tyranny. Disease,
compassion of orthodoxy. It is not then               not health, is the tyranny. The unbinding
surprising that we are not sensitive to the           of Prometheus would consist in not so
tragic irony in the portrayal of a god                much the loosing of his chains as in the
whose name we remember but whose                      opening of his eyes and the realigning of
crime we hardly comprehend. We read                   his mind and heart with the unseen but
Aeschylus but can see only Goethe and                 real order of Zeus.

   Friedrich Solmsen, Hesiod and Aeschylus,           Aeschylus,” Journal of Hellenic Studies, 76
(Ithaca, N.Y., 1949), pp. 124-57. 2Hugh Lloyd-        (1956), 56. *Nicolaus Wecklein, introduction to
Jones, Justice of Zeus (Berkeley, 1983), p. 102.      his edition of Prometheus Bound (Boston,
3D.J. Conacher, Aeschylus’ Prometheus Bound:          1897), p. 27. YEirik Vandvik, Prometheus of
A Literary Commentary (Toronto, 1980), pp.            Hesiod and Aeschylus (Oslo, 1942); Eric
133 ff. His chapter “The Zeus Problem” is a           Voegelin, World of the Polis, vol. 2 o f Order
good but incomplete summary of the various            and History (Baton Rouge, 1957), pp. 243-62,
interpretations. 4Mark Griffith, Authenticity of      and Science, Politics and Gnosticism: Two
Prometheus Bound (Cambridge, Eng., 1976),             Essays (Chicago, 1968), pp. 34-40; Leo Strauss,
though his central objections are stylistic.          “The Liberalism of Classical Political
addition to the above, see: Leon Golden, In           Philosophy,” in Liberalism Ancient and Modern
Praise o f Prometheus: Humanism and Ra-               (New York, 1968), pp. 41-43. ‘Osee Conacher,
tionalism in Aeschylean Thought (Chapel Hill,         pp. 22-23; Lloyd-Jones, Justice of Zeus, p. 110,
N.C., 1962); David Grene’s introduction to his        n. 110; Wecklein, p. 27. ”Vandvik, pp. 5,29; see
translation of the Prometheus Bound (New              also Jon D. Mikalson, Athenian Popular
York, 1968); Mark Griffith’s introduction to his      Religion (Chapel Hill, N.C., 1983), p. 18. Though
edition of the Prometheus Bound (Cambridge,           his work draws primarily upon evidence from
Eng., 1983); E.A. Havelock, Prometheus (Seat-         the late fifth and the fourth centuries (405-323
tle, 1968) [Revealingly, the title of the 1950 edi-   B.C.), it seems reasonable that the Athenians
tion of this book was The Crucifixionof Intellec-     were not more pious and devoted to the gods
tual Man.); Karl Kerenyi, Prometheus; Ar-             than they were in the early fifth century. The
chetypal Image of Human Existence (New                trend was the other way, from piety toward
York, 1963); H.D.F. Kitto, Greek Tragedy: A           skepticism. See also Andre-Jean Festugikre,
Literary Study (New York, 1954); Anthony J.           Personal Religion Among the Greeks (Berkeley,
Podlecki, Political Background of Aeschylean          Calif., 1954), pp. 27 ff. 120n this question of the
Tragedy (Ann Arbor, Mich., 1966); Lois Spatz,         position of the play within the trilogy, see M.L.
Aeschylus (Boston, 1982); George Thomson,             West, “The Prometheus Trilogy,” Journal of
Aeschylus and Athens: A Study in the Social           Hellenic Studies, 99 (1979), 131 ff. West, unlike
Origins of Drama (London, 1946). GPodlecki,           most commentators, argues that the play was
pp. 102-3. ’Hugh Lloyd-Jones, “Zeus in                not the first but the middle drama: “The plan of

40                                                                                        Winter 1986
                         LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
                  ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
the trilogy was then Crime-Punishment-               tive analysts of the nature of Zeus’s regime.
Reconciliation. This and not Punishment-             They are, after all, only soldier-servants.
Reconciliation-(?) is surely the scheme that         Moreover, the peace of every state, republics as
would naturally have occurred to the poet.”          well as tyrannies, is guaranteed in some
I3Wecklein, p. 19; Vandvik, pp. 5, 29. I4Arthur      measure by “strength and violence.” Order in
Pickard-Cambridge, Dramatic Festivals of             the soul does not, this side of the parousia,
Athens (Oxford, 1968), p. 86. Regarding selec-       establish order in the community. That Zeus
tion of a poet’s works for production in the City    employs force in the execution of his designs
Dionysia, see p. 84. Regarding the behavior, at-     does no automatic discredit to his regime; and
titudes, and tastes of the audiences, see pp.        that that regime is “new” counts for nothing in
272-80. ISHesiod, Theogony. Works and Days           deciding whether that guaranteeing force is
. . . (Harmondsworth, Eng., 1973), p. 74, 1 . 484.   justly deployed in the case of Prometheus.
I6Hesiod, Theogony, 1 1 . 550-51, cited in           Z0Recalltoo that it was this expelled tyrant, Hip-
Kerenyi, p. 47. I7See Mikalson, chap. 1: “The        pias, who guided the Persians onto the plain at
Priority of the Gods.” See also pp. 30 ff. The       Marathon (Herodotus VI: 102). See Podlecki, p.
Greeks believed that the gods intervened in           117. 21Lloyd-Jones,Justice ofZeus,p. 103. 22See
human affairs when their own prerogatives            Golden, pp. 101-2; Conacher, p. 70; Solmsen,
were threatened: in cases of murder, treason,        pp. 135, 137; Thomson, pp. 322-23. 23See
the violation of oaths, and various impieties        especially Vandvik’s analysis of the lo scene,
toward sacred places and objects - such as the       pp. 58-59. 24Conacher, p. 35. 25Karl Kerenyi,
theft of fire from Zeus’s hearth.18 The edition of   Gods of the Greeks (London, 1951), p. 207.
the play I have used is Prometheus Bound             26Voegelin, World of the Polis, pp. 259-60.
(Baltimore, 1961). IgStrength and Violence are       271bid.,p. 260. 28Strauss, p. 42.
loyal but not necessarily very bright or percep-

Modern Age                                                                                          41
                                 LICENSED TO UNZ.ORG
                          ELECTRONIC REPRODUCTION PROHIBITED
You can also read